Legal Theory Blog |
|
All the theory that fits! Home This is Lawrence Solum's legal theory weblog. Legal Theory Blog comments and reports on recent scholarship in jurisprudence, law and philosophy, law and economic theory, and theoretical work in substantive areas, such as constitutional law, cyberlaw, procedure, criminal law, intellectual property, torts, contracts, etc. RSS Links for Legal Theory Blog --Lawrence B. Solum (My Homepage at the University of Illinois) --My College of Law Directory Page --My Philosophy Department Directory Page --Email me --Legal Theory Annex (All the theory that does not fit.) --Legal Theory Lexicon (Basic concepts in legal theory for first year law students.) --My Publications on SSRN Noteworthy Posts Hiring Trends at 18 "Top" American Law Schools 2005-06 Report on Law School Entry Level Hiring 2004-05 Report on Law School Entry Level Hiring 2003-04 Report on Entry Level Hiring Legal Theory Bookclub: Lessig's Free Culture Getting to Formalism Water Wells and MP3 Files: The Economics of Intellectual Property Do Humans Have Character Traits? Naturalistic Ethics The Case for Strong Stare Decisis, or Why Should Neoformalists Care About Precedent? Part I: The Three Step Argument Part II: Stare Decisis and the Ratchet Part III: Precedent and Principle Fear and Loathing in New Haven A Neoformalist Manifesto Understanding the Confirmation Wars: The Role of Political Ideology and Judicial Philosophy Breaking the Deadlock: Reflections on the Confirmation Wars Going Nuclear: The Constitutionality of Recess Appointments to Article III Courts Archives 09/01/2002 - 09/30/2002 01/01/2003 - 01/31/2003 02/01/2003 - 02/28/2003 03/01/2003 - 03/31/2003 04/01/2003 - 04/30/2003 05/01/2003 - 05/31/2003 06/01/2003 - 06/30/2003 07/01/2003 - 07/31/2003 08/01/2003 - 08/31/2003 09/01/2003 - 09/30/2003 10/01/2003 - 10/31/2003 11/01/2003 - 11/30/2003 12/01/2003 - 12/31/2003 01/01/2004 - 01/31/2004 02/01/2004 - 02/29/2004 03/01/2004 - 03/31/2004 04/01/2004 - 04/30/2004 05/01/2004 - 05/31/2004 06/01/2004 - 06/30/2004 07/01/2004 - 07/31/2004 08/01/2004 - 08/31/2004 09/01/2004 - 09/30/2004 10/01/2004 - 10/31/2004 11/01/2004 - 11/30/2004 12/01/2004 - 12/31/2004 01/01/2005 - 01/31/2005 02/01/2005 - 02/28/2005 03/01/2005 - 03/31/2005 04/01/2005 - 04/30/2005 05/01/2005 - 05/31/2005 06/01/2005 - 06/30/2005 07/01/2005 - 07/31/2005 08/01/2005 - 08/31/2005 09/01/2005 - 09/30/2005 10/01/2005 - 10/31/2005 11/01/2005 - 11/30/2005 12/01/2005 - 12/31/2005 01/01/2006 - 01/31/2006 02/01/2006 - 02/28/2006 03/01/2006 - 03/31/2006 04/01/2006 - 04/30/2006 05/01/2006 - 05/31/2006 06/01/2006 - 06/30/2006 07/01/2006 - 07/31/2006 Blogosphere New: --PrawfsBlog (Group BLog) --Balkinization (Jack Balkin) --Crescat Sententia (Group Blog) --Crooked Timber (Group Blog) --De Novo (Group Blog) --Desert Landscapes (Group Blog) --Discourse.Net (Michael Froomkin) --Displacement of Concepts (Group Blog) --Election Law (Rick Hasen) --Freedom to Tinker (Ed Felten) --The Garden of Forking Paths --How Appealing (Howard Bashman) --Instapundit (Glenn Reynolds) --Is That Legal? (Eric Muller) --Law & Society Weblog (Group Blog) --The Leiter Reports (Brian Leiter) --Lessig Blog (Lawrence Lessig) --Marstonalia (Brett Marston) --Paper Chase @ Jurist (Bernard Hibbitts) --Political Arguments (Group Blog) --ProfessorBainbridge.com (Stephen Bainbridge) --Pea Soup (Group Blog) --Punishment Theory (Group Blog) --The Right Coast (Group Blog) --SCOTUS Blog (Group Blog) --Sentencing Law and Policy (Douglas Berman --Statutory Construction Zone (Gary O'Connor) --TaxProf Blog (Paul Caron) --Volokh Conspiracy (Group Blog) Websites of Interest +Arts and Letters Daily +Conference Alerts +Daily Whirl +fa.philos-l +Economic Theory News +Encyclopedia of Law and Economics +Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program (U.C. Berkeley) eScholarship Repository +Law and Politics Book Reviews +Metapsychology Book Reviews +Notre Dame Philosophical Review +Online Papers in Philosophy +PoliticalTheory.info +SSRN Most Recent Uploads More Blogs of Interest --Althouse (Ann Althouse) --Asymmetrical Information (Jane Galt) --bIPlog (Group Blog) --The Blawg Review (Group Blog) --Brad DeLong --The Buck Stops Here (Stuart Buck) --Copyfight (Group Blog) --A Copyfighter's Musings (Derek Slater) --The Curmudgeonly Clerk --Daniel Drezner --Discriminations (John and Jessie Rosenberg) --Eastmania (Wayne Eastman) --EveTushnet.com (Eve Tushnet) --Freespace (Timothy Sandefur) --Furdlog Frank Field --Ideoblog (Larry Ribstein) --The Importance Of (Ernest Miller) --The Indiana Law Blog (Marcia J. Oddi) --Infothought (Seth Finkelstein) --IPKat (Jeremy Phillips and Ilanah Simon) --Law and Economics Blog (Greg Goelzhauser) --Law Dork (Chris Geidner) --Law Meme (Group Blog) --Lee Blog Edward Lee --Legal Ramblings (Steven Wu) --Lenz Blog (Karl-Friedrich Lenz) --Letters of Marque (Heidi Bond) --The Light of Reason (Arthur Silber) --Matthew Yglesias --philosophy.com (Gary Sauer-Thompson ) --Public Defender Dude --Rodger A. Payne's Blog --Southern Appeal (Group Blog) --Strange Doctrines/A> --Susan Crawford blog --A Taxing Blog (Group Blog) --That's News to Me (Group Blog) --Thoughts Arguments and Rants (Brian Weatherson) --Three Years of Hell to Become the Devil --The Trademark Blog (Martin Schwimmer) --Troppo Armadillo (Ken Parish) --Technology 360 --Tutissima Cassis (Nate Oman) --Unlearned Hand --Weatherall's Law (Kim Weatherall) --WENDY.SELTZER.ORG (Wendy Seltzer) --yin (Tung Yin) Legal Theory Programs & Websites --Arizona State Committee on Law and Philosophy --Cambridge Forum for Legal and Political Philosophy --Columbia Law School Center for Law and Philosophy --Columbia Legal Theory Workhsop --Georgetown University Law Center--Colloquium on Constitutional Law and Theory --Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program (U.C. Berkeley) --Kadish Center for Morality, Law, and Public Affairs (U.C. Berkeley) --NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political and Social Philosophy --Oxford Jurisprudence Discussion Group --Oxford Legal Philosophy --Oxford Centre for Ethics & Philosophy of Law --Queen's University Belfast Forlum for Law and Philosophy --Rutgers Institute for Law and Philosophy --UCLA Legal Theory Workshop --University of Pennsylvania Institute for Law and Philosophy --University College London: Colloquium in Legal and Social Philosophy --University of Chicago Law And Philosophy Workshops --University of Chicago: John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics Workshop --University of San Diego Institute for Law and Philosophy --University of Texas Law and Philosophy Program --Yale Law School: Legal Theory Workshop Links to Law School Workshops +Australian National University Faculty Events +Boston University +Buffalo +Columbia Center for Law and Economic Studies +Florida State +Fordham +George Mason +George Washington--IP Workshop Series +Georgetown Colloquium on Intellectual Property & Technology Law +Georgetown Law Workshops +Georgetown Law and Economics Workshop +Georgetown Law & Economics Workshop Series +Hofstra +University of Illinois +Lewis & Clark +Loyola Marymount +New York University +NYU Legal History Colloquium +Northwestern Law Colloquium +Oxford Law Events +Rutgers, Camden +Stanford Center for Internet & Society +Stanford Law School Olin Series +UCLA Colloquium +UCLA Legal History Workshop +UCLA Tax Policy --University of Chicago: John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics Workshop +University of Michigan Law and Economics +University of San Diego Colloquium Series +University of Texas Colloquium Series +Vanderbilt Scholarly Programs & Events Calendar +Villanova +Washington & Lee Faculty Workshops +Yale Law, Economics & Organizations Workshop Calendars & Events +Aristotelian Society +British Society for Ethical Theory +Conference Alerts +Events in Analytic Philosophy in Europe (and Overseas Countries) +The Philosophical Calendar +Philosophy Now Calendar +Political Science Online Upcoming Conferences +SSRN Professional Announcements Other Programs --Australian National University, Research School of Social Science, Philosophy Seminars --Boston University Philosophy Colloquia --Brown University Philosoophy Upcoming Events George Mason Workshop in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics --Harvard University, Philosophy Colloquia --MIT Philosophy Colloquia --New York University, Philosophy Events --Oxford: Events at the Faculty of Philosophy --Princeton University: Philosophy Department Talks --Princeton University: Political Philosophy Colloquium --Princeton University: Public Law Colloquium --Princeton University: Seminar in Law and Public Affairs --Tulane Philosophy and Center for Ethics & Public Affairs Seminars --University College, London: Political Theory Seminars --University of Arizona Philosophy Colloquia --University of Bristol Philosophy Research Seminars --University of California at Berkeley Philosophy Events --University of California at San Diego Philosophy Colloquia --University of Chicago Political Theory Workshop --University of London, School of Advanced Study, Philosophy Programme --University of Manchester Politics & Philosophy Research Seminars --University of Melbourne Philosophy Events --University of North Carolina: Philosophy Speakers --University of Pennsylvania: Philosophy Colloquiua --University of Pittsburgh Philosophy Calendar --Yale Philosophy Department Talks Some Legal Theorist Homepages --Robert Alexy (Christian Albrechts University Kiel) --Randy Barnett (BU) --Brian Bix (Minnesota) --Jules Coleman(Yale Law & Philosophy) --Ronald Dworkin(NYU & University College) --John Finnis(Oxford and Notre Dame) --John Gardner (Oxford) --Brian Leiter (Texas) --Micahel Moore (Illinois) --Dennis Patterson (Rutgers, Camden) --Stephen Perry (NYU) --Richard Posner (University of Chicago & USCA7) --Joseph Raz (Oxford and Columbia) --Jeremy Waldron (Columbia More to come! Journals Specializing in Legal Philosophy --American Journal of Jurisprudence --The Journal of Philosophy, Science, and Law --Law and Philosophy --Law and Social Inquiry --Legal Theory --Oxford Journal of Legal Studies Legal Theory Resources on the Web Entries from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy +Austin, John +justice, distributive +justice, as a virtue +legal philosophy, economic analysis of law +legal reasoning, interpretation and coherence +legal rights +liberalism +libertarianism +naturalism in legal philosophy +nature of law +nature of law, legal positivism +nature of law, pure theory of law +republicanism From the Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence +Natural Law Theory: The Modern Tradition From the Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies +Law as an Autonomous Discipline From the Examined Life A Critical Introduction to Liberalism Papers & Articles +Virtue Jurisprudence Organizations +American Political Science Association(APSA) +American Society for Political and Legal Philosophy (ASPLP) +Association of American Law Schools(AALS) +Internationale Vereinigung fur Rechts und Sozialphilosophie(IVR) +Law and Society Association +Midwest Political Science Association (MPSA) My Postal Address Lawrence B. Solum University of Illinois College of Law 504 East Pennsylvania Ave Champaign, IL 61820 USA |
Sunday, April 30, 2006
Legal Theory Calendar
University of Texas Law: James Spriggs (UC Davis) "Courting the Public: Judicial Behavior and Public Views of Court Decisions"
Oxford Criminology Seminar Series 2005/06: David Green, The Politics of Tradegy: Comparing Responses to Child-on-Child Homicide Organised by: Oxford Law Faculty: Kai Moller, Seminar Series on Robert Alexy's " A Theory of Constitutional Rights": Introduction
Oxford Comparative Law Discussion Group: Ruth Sefton-Green, French and English Legal Scholarship: Swings and Roundabouts Oxford Public International Law Discussion Group: Dr Susan Marks, State-Centrism, International Law and the Anxieties of Influence Fordham Law: Yochai Benkler, Professor of Law, Yale Law School University College London Jurisprudence Meeting: Thomas Ricard, "The Illusion of Neutrality" David Prendergast, "How Law Legitimates Itself"
Oxford Law Faculty: Mr Justice Anselmo Reyes, "Sea Changes: Reflections on the Encounter between Common Law Judges and Personal Laws" Legal Theory Lexicon: Overlapping Consensus & Incompletely Theorized Agreements
For a short time, the ability to see this pattern may be exhilarating. You begin to see big patterns that transcend courses and doctrines. But after a while, exhilaration may give way to depression. If all the great debates in legal theory boil down to debates about the deepest questions of moral and political philosophy, then the question arises, "Can we make any progress?" Because it sure doesn't look like the debates between deontology and consequentialism or between libertarians and communitarians are going to be decisively resolved any time soon. And that is where today's Legal Theory Lexicon comes into the picture. Even if the deep debates of moral and political philosophy are irresolvable, there may be other ways to make progress in legal theory. In particular, we may be able to use the ideas of "incompletely theorized agreements" (associated with Cass Sunstein) or "overlapping consensus" (associated with John Rawls) to break the impasse on the deep questions. The basic idea is simple. We cannot agree on the deep questions, so go shallow. Find the level at which those who disagree on the deep can nonetheless find common ground. John Rawls calls the idea of common ground by the name "overlapping consensus." Cass Sunstein calls a similar idea, "incompletely theorized agreement." But both Sunstein and Rawls express a similar intuition. When you cannot reach agreement at the deep end of the pool of ideas, head for the shallow end! Deep and Shallow I suspect that you've already gotten it! But just to make sure, let's work through the ideas one by one. The first idea we need is the one that I have expressed by the metaphor of deep and shallow reasons. The metaphor is based on the idea that particular applications (e.g. particular questions of legal doctrine) are at the surface, they are in the shallow end of the pool of ideas. Beneath the surface of particular issues in legal doctrine and legislative policy are deeper disagreements. Disagreements about the a surface level question (e.g. the precise contours of the mailbox rule in contract law) lead to beneath-the-surface issues (e.g. the nature of offer and acceptance) and then to still-deeper issues (e.g. the basis for contractual obligation) and finally to the deepest questions (e.g. the nature of moral obligation). You might picture a chain of reasons, stretching from the surface of legal doctrine down to the depths of political and moral philosophy. Overlapping Consensus John Rawls developed the idea of an "overlapping consensus" as part of the work that led up to his book Political Liberalism. The idea emerged as part of Rawls's work on what he called the problem of stability. In a society governed by Rawls's theory (justice as fairness), the guarantee of basic liberties would mean that individual citizens would be free to adopt their own views about morality and religion. As a result, Rawls argued, it was likely that a variety of comprehensive religious and moral doctrines would emerge. Rawls believed that this fact of pluralism posed a problem for his theory. How could justice as fairness be stable (or reproduce itself) given the plurality of viewpoints that is bound to emerge and persist under conditions of freedom? Rawls's answer to this question was based on the idea that divergent moral and religious conceptions of the good could (despite their diversity) converge on some common ground. That is, citizens who held a plurality of religious and moral beliefs could nonetheless agree on the constitutional essentials--the basic constitutional principles necessary for a society to satisfy the demands of justice as fairness. This meant that different citizens would support justice as fairness for different reasons. Catholics might affirm justice as fairness for reasons found within the Catholic natural law tradition, while secular humanists might affirm the same (or similar) ideas about justice for different reasons. Although a deep consensus might on justice as fairness might be impossible, an "overlapping consensus," Rawls argued, is possible. Incompletely Theorized Agreements Cass Sunstein has a related but different idea. Here is a summary from his article in the Harvard Law Review:
This sort of agreement is incompletely theorized in the sense that it is incompletely specified -- a familiar phenomenon with constitutional provisions and regulatory standards in administrative law. Incompletely specified agreements have distinctive social uses. They may permit acceptance of a general aspiration when people are unclear about what the aspiration means, and in this sense, they can maintain a measure of both stability and flexibility over time. At the same time, they can conceal the fact of large- scale social disagreement about particular cases. There is a second and quite different kind of incompletely theorized agreement. People may agree on a mid-level principle but disagree both about the more general theory that accounts for it and about outcomes in particular cases. They may believe that government cannot discriminate on the basis of race, without settling on a large-scale theory of equality, and without agreeing whether government may enact affirmative action programs or segregate prisons when racial tensions are severe. The connections are left unclear, either in people's minds or in authoritative public documents, between the mid- level principle and general theory; the connection is equally unclear between the mid-level principle and concrete cases. So too, people may think that government may not regulate speech unless it can show a clear and present danger, but fail to settle whether this principle is founded in utilitarian or Kantian considerations, and disagree about whether the principle allows government to regulate a particular speech by members of the Ku Klux Klan. My special interest here is in a third kind of phenomenon -- incompletely theorized agreements on particular outcomes, accompanied by agreements on the low-level principles that account for them. These terms contain some ambiguities. There is no algorithm by which to distinguish between a high-level theory and one that operates at an intermediate or low level. We might consider Kantianism and utilitarianism as conspicuous examples of high-level theories and see legal illustrations in the many (academic) efforts to understand such areas as tort law, contract law, free speech, and the law of equality to be undergirded by highly abstract theories of the right or the good. By contrast, we might think of low-level principles as including most of the ordinary material of legal doctrine -- the general class of principles and justifications that are not said to derive from any particular large theories of the right or the good, that have ambiguous relations to large theories, and that are compatible with more than one such theory. [Cass Sunstein, Incompletely Theorized Agreements, 108 Harv. L. Rev. 1733, 1739-40 (1995)] The alternative is to see whether you can find a different level at which the dispute can be resolved. One possibility is that you can find convergence at the surface level. It seems as if deontologists and utilitarians disagree, but perhaps you can craft consequentialist arguments that converge with the arguments of fairness. Another possibility is that you will be able to find converged on what Sunstein calls "mid-level principles." For example, both consequentialists and deontologists might be able to agree that contract formation (normally) requires that both parties manifest and intention to be bound--although they would have different reasons for affirming this proposition. Conclusion The move to "overlapping consensus" or "incompletely theorized agreements" is one of the niftiest and most useful in contemporary legal theory. Add it your personal legal theory toolbox! Saturday, April 29, 2006
Legal Theory Bookworm The Legal Theory Bookworm recommends An Army of Davids : How Markets and Technology Empower Ordinary People to Beat Big Media, Big Government, and Other Goliaths by Glenn Reynolds. Here's a blurb:
Download of the Week The Download of the Week is Killing in Good Conscience: Comments on Sunstein and Vermeule's Lesser Evil Argument for Capital Punishment by Eric Blumenson. Here is the Abstract:
Friday, April 28, 2006
Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Howard Bashman Howard Bashman provided wonderful comments on the last panel! I just want to say that Howard and his website, How Appealing, are absolutely and totally amazing. It was a pleasure to meet him in person. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Christine Hurt Christine Hurt's paper (coauthored with Tung Yin) is Blogging While Untenured and Other Extreme Sports. Yin and Hurt are interested in the costs and benefits of blogging for untenured legal scholars. Among Hurt's many interesting points is that an academic blog can actually make scholarship more efficient: this is especially true for bloggers, like Hurt, whose blog is closely related to the primary focus of her scholarship. Another point that Hurt emphasized is the potential for blogging to create positive reputational and networking effects--if the quality of the blogging is high. Of course, there is a converse risk--the risk of negative reputational effects and offending potential colleagues. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Ann Althouse Ann Althouse's paper Why a Narrowly Defined Legal Scholarship Blog Is Not What I Want: An Argument in Pseudo-Blog Form has much to say that's really interesting. She certainly makes an eloquent case for "free form" multitopic blogging. I think she's right: free form blogging can be cool. But this begs an important question--and the question that is the theme of the conference--the role of blogs, if any, in legal scholarship. One reaction that I had to Ann's paper is the following. Academics should be free, just as free as anyone else, to blog recreationally. Of course. But academics should also be free to pursue blogging as a form of scholarship. This leads to an interesting question: can free form blogging be combined with scholarly blogging? My off-the-cuff reaction to this question is "no." Or at least, "probably not." One reason for this answer is simply practical. Academic blogging mixed with free form blogging is hard to differentiate from blogging that does not aspire to the standards of scholarship--that is, to rigor and an intentional focus on truth. A related point is that it will very difficult for academic administrators to decide how to reward mixed blogging. And if blogging isn't rewarded, then it will tend to fade away, because academics will tend to gravitate towards those scholarly activities that do recieve extrinsic rewards. This is especially likely to be true for those who don't yet have blogs and who face large start up costs before their blogs can attract significant numbers of readers. Having said all that, I do not mean to disagree with anything that Althouse says. A mixed blog can be fun and rewarding. And anyone who wants to try this out ought to give it a whirl. But there is another option--it's just as easy to set up two blogs as it to set up one. (Almost, anyway.) Randy Barnett conceived this point in terms of the idea of "opt in"--idea his, term "opt in" mine. If you want your blog to be treated as serious scholarship, you need to "opt in" by making the focus of the blog serious and scholarly. No one should be required to opt in--that's a matter of preference. But no one should be discouraged from making the judgment that mixed blogs, blogs about politics and life, and blogs that routinely present opinions without warrants are not scholarship. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Larry Ribstein My colleague, Larry Ribstein, is up at the Bloggership conference. His paper, The Public Face of Scholarship, is available for download from SSRN. Larry has a nice typology of academic blogs or of academic blog posts:
2. The Blogicle--the short scholarly article as blog post 3. Self-promotion--blogging about one's own "long form" legal scholarship 4. Scholarly public engagement--the blog post as "op/ed"
Ribstein's discussion of bias among professional journalists was also quite interesting. Why might professional journalists be biased? One possibility is that the market wants entertainment and journalists are simply responding to the demand. Another theory is that journalists are trying meet reader's expectations about what reality is: journalists who want to be perceived as accurate must meet these expectations. Yet another possibility is that reader's are biased and want stories that confirm their preexisting biases. Those are all demand based theories. On the supply side, Ribstein explores the possibility that journalists come into the profession with biases. For example, journalists may choose their profession on grounds other than wealth and hence may have a bias against the wealthy. Ribstein then suggests that PEAPs may actually change reader expectations. His final point is that PEAPs might turn academic bloggers into "public intellectuals"--that is, there may be incentives for academic bloggers to opine on subjects they know very little about. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Eugene Volokh Eugene Volokh, another superstar blogger, is speaking at the bloggership conference at Harvard Law School. His paper, Scholarship, Blogging and Trade-offs: On Discovering, Disseminating, and Doing, is available on SSRN. Eugene's talk, however, was about the relationship between freedom of speech and blogging. The first part of his talk was a very rapid survey of varous relevant bits of law. One interesting bit concerned the state statutes that protect "off premises lawful activity" from retaliatory firings by employers. "Blogging" may be protected by such statutes--which were designed, in part, to protect smokers. Another part of the talk concerned the question whehter blogs should receive some sort of "extra" free speech protection--something like journalistic privileges. In particular, Eugene argued that blogs have a special value as a check on the "mainstream media." One interesting question is whether blogs must be treated as well as other media: for example, must blogs be exempted from campaign finance laws, if other media are exempted? Eugene argued that "strict scrutiny" would apply and hence that the exemption must be afforded blogs. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Glenn Reynolds Glenn Reynolds is discussing Libel in the Blogosphere: Some Preliminary Thoughts. Glenn's blog, Instapundit has been incredibly important to the emergence of the legal and law professor blogosphere. A link from Glenn Reynolds can introduce thousands of new readers to a blog. Is there anything interesting to say about blogs and defamation? Glenn's talk addresses the question whether, as a practical matter, bloggers are likely to be sued for (or held liable) for defeamation. He concludes that they aren't: bloggers don't have deep pockets; bloggers tend to blog opinion more than fact; blogs tend to link to sources when they make factual claims. One of the interesting "factoids" in his talk conerns the statutes that protect "off-premises lawful activity" or "off-premises recreational activity" from private retaliation by employers. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Michael Froomkin Michael Froomkin is up! He begins by noting that he has three kinds of blogs:
A personal blog--Discourse.net, and Teaching blogs--several of these Froomkin suggests that blogging is frequently done in a "different voice," and that in his case, he writes differently for each of his different blogs. Blogging is less formal. Blogging, Froomkin, concludes is good for activism, for engaging as a public intellectual, and for writing outside of one's own subdiscipline. Froomkin also addresses the role of blogging in the dissemination of legal scholarship. He suggests that "Larry Solum reads to much," and suggests the creation of a collaborative site that facilitates identifying and praising new legal scholarshp: jotwell.com. Blogging from the Blogging Conference: Randy Barnett Randy Barnett is one of the commentators on the second panel of the bloggership scholarship hosted by the Berkman Center at Harvard (schedule here & podcast here). Barnett's comment pointed to the "alligator in the bathtup" when it comes to law professor bloggers. If you have knocked around the legal academy for a long time, you will know that flight from serous legal scholarship is a persistent feature of the the legal academy. Many law professors are passionate about scholarship--about creating new knowledge in a rigorous way. But many law professors search for something else--alternatives to serious long-form legal scholarship--whether it be the role of "public intellectual" or "advocacy" or writing novels. Barnett begins with the point that most law blogging does not purport to be serious scholarship, but some is and more could be. Blogging is a medium and not the message. BArnett says that there is big "BUT" about blogging. The "but" is the "flight from scholarship." It is, he says, a perennial problem for law professors: most law professors, he says, don't like legal scholarship. And this leads them to say that things the do like to do are legal scholarship. This is reflected in the divisions on many faculties between those who do and those who do not engage in serious legal scholarship. So blogging may be, for some, a flight from scholarship. Why do many (or most) law professors not like scholarship? That it is hard and it is very hard to do well. Blogging is easier than scholarship! (Randy, you try doing Legal Theory Blog! Randy is sitting next to me now, and reminds me that he did say, spontantously in Q & A, that LTB was probably a lot of work.) Finally, Barnett argues that there are things that can be discovered in long-form legal scholarship that can only be discovered in that way. And I agree with this! I've had this experience myself many times. But I would add that blogging can interact with and supplement long-form legal scholarship in a variety of ways! Barnett gives the example of his own work on the Ninth Amendment: the long form is the only way that he can go through all of the detailed historical evidence that is necessary to make a sound originalist argument about the meaning of the Ninth. Blogging about Blogging about the Bloggershp Conference My apologies for the silliness. Check out:
Live-blogging the Bloggership conference! by Ann Althouse A Discussion About Law Professor Blogging by Eric Muller Harvard Bloggership Conference by Jim Lindgren Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Orin Kerr Orin Kerr is up now. Orin wrote a terrific paper: Blogs and the Legal Academy, which you can download from SSRN. Kerr's thesis that blogs have an inherent problem which stems from the fact that blog posts are viewed in "Reverse Chronological Order" or RCO. That is an important feature of blogs! Kerr argues that this means that Blogs do not lend themselves to mulling and deep reflection on a problem. And Kerr argues that "mulling" is the way that really important legal scholarship gets done. And I think Kerr is completely wrong--that he has made a fundamental error. One of the most wonderful things about blogs is that they provide an important mechanism for "mulling:" for engaging in extended discussions about important ideas. If you want to see an example of the way that blogs can facilitate "mulling," and extended discussion of an idea, take a look at this post by Jack Balkin or this post by Eugene Volokh and also this one. Or take a look at any one of the dozens of serious scholarship blogs! Another problem with Kerr's point is that RCO does not dominate blogging in quite they way that he thinks. Blogs are archived and full-text searchable--that means that many people get to blogs from Google. And blogs can build their own interfacts: for example, I build a Table of Contents style interface for the blog that serves as a separate archive for the Legal Theory Lexicon. Kerr makes another point about blogs--one that I agree with. He makes the point that bloggers tend to care about sitemeter--the number of daily hits they get. And caring about that may tilt blogs in favor of popularized content. Kerr says that he wants anyone live blogging to say that there was thunderous applause. Well, there was applause. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Jim Lindgren Jim Lindgren is commenting on the papers from the first session. Jim is one of the very best empirical scholars in the business. Jim suggests three different approaches to the question whether blogging is legal scholarshp. He suggests that this question should be met with another question: "Why do you want to know?" Lindgren suggests that for some purposes it is, pointing to a post of his own that presented extensive empirical data on the prevalence of black conservatives. Lindgren points out that most legal scholarship is not on SSRN--which he says focuses on law and economics. (I'm not sure that is right--especially not today.) Lindgren then discussed his own exerience with his investigation of the scholarship in Arming America : The Origins of a National Gun Culture by Michael Bellesiles. One of the points that Lindgren made is that a blog post by Glenn Reynolds had a tremendous impact on the dissemination of his article. Publication in the Yale Law Journal, Lindgren observes, hardly created a ripple, but the blogs resulted in more than 50,000 downloads of his article. Jim's point is an important one--blogs play a unique role in acting as a special kind of intermediary between traditional legal scholarship and public intellectual discourse. The live webcase is available at this link. Blogging from the Bloggership Conference: Kate Litvak Kate Litvak is speaking at the bloggership conference at Harvard. You can follow her talk online, scroll down for the link. Litvak's focus is on larger trends in legal scholarship, including SSRN, the declining role of law reviews, long-distance co-authorship, interdisciplinarity & the influx of non-law PhDs into the legal academy, increasing "technicalization" (e.g. more sophisticated economic techniques), the high cost of producing large-scale empirical legal scholarship, the increasing "gap" between the legal academy and the legal profession, and the globalization. So, Litvak asks, how important is blogging as compared to these other trends? Her thesis is that blogging is not as important as these other trends. In particular, she argues that blogs do not play an important role in the dissemination of legal scholarship. Litvak asks, why should she go to a blog, when she can search for relevant scholarship on SSRN? Litvak then analogizes "blogs" to "water coolers" in the faculty lounge--a "bugged water cooler." It seems to me that this analogy is both right and wrong. Right, because there are some blogs that are very much like water cooler conversations. Wrong, for three reasons: (1) wrong, because the term "blogged" connotes and denotes secret monitoring and blogs are self-consciously published; (2) wrong, because the conversational nature of many blog posts is not an inherent feature of blogs, it is a characteristic of the content generated by certain bloggers--blogs can be as serious or frivlous as you the blogger wishes; (3) wrong, because Litvak's analogy mistakes content for form--blogs themselves are nothing more than a set of interlinked webpages and software for their publication. Litvak also makes the argument that blogs do not advance serious arguments. Again, I think she is right and wrong. Right, because there are certainly bloggers who do not advance serious arguments. Wrong, because this is not an inherent feature of blogs. Indeed, it is possible for blogs to produce extended serious commentary on new ideas. One example from this blog is my extended commentary on Larry Lessig's Free Culture--Legal Theory Bookclub: Lessig's Free Culture, which was later published by the Texas Law Review. You can download Litvak's paper from SSRN: Blog as a Bugged Water Cooler. A Blogger's Tale
In September of 2002, I started a blog. On a whim. I barely knew what a blog was, and I certainly didn’t know what to do with one. Like a lot of bloggers, at first I didn’t even know that the word “blog” was short for weblog. And I had no clue as to what a web log was—beyond the obvious, that is was some kind of “log” on the world wide “web.” To be candid, I had started to notice the word “blog” popping up in “cool” venues, and I hated the idea that I was already “behind the curve.” So, I looked at a few blogs. I don’t remember which ones, but I began to understand that a blog consisted of “posts” or entries that formed a kind of online diary or journal. I got the sense that blogs could be about almost anything—serious, frivolous, political, cultural, personal. Whatever. I posted some posts, got busy with other things, and let the blog lie dormant until January of 2003, when I started to post again on a regular basis. I called the blog “Legal Theory Blog.” I knew that other law professors had blogs—I think that I knew about the Volokh Conspiracy, a group blog organized by Eugene Volokh of the University of California at Los Angeles Law School and I might have been aware of “Instapundit,” a solo effort by Glenn Reynolds of the University of Tennessee Law School. I had a certain idea about what the blog might accomplish, based on something else that I was just beginning to use extensively as a research tool—the Social Science Citation Network, a website and service that provides access on the Internet to scholarly papers in a variety of disciplines including law. I wanted to do a blog with a focus on “legal theory” broadly conceived as encompassing a variety of interdisciplinary approaches to normative and positive legal scholarship. What a geek. I thought to myself: “I’m reading these papers on SSRN in draft. I could blog about some of the papers that I read.” It seemed to me that there might be half a dozen potential readers, who would be interested in my postings about legal theory papers. Secretly, I hope that if the blog were a giant success it might attract a few dozen readers on a semi-regular basis. And I said to myself, “What the hell, if no one reads it, I’ll just stop doing it.” As I recall, my expectations were rather low: I believed that it was “too late” for entry into the blogging market—which was already dominated by a few “big blogs.” Were it not for some positive feedback, I’m almost sure my career as a blogger would have ended a few weeks into my second foray. At first the feedback came in tiny dribs and drabs. I can actually name the two people who are most responsible for the continued existence of “Legal Theory Blog.” Chris Bertram and Nathan Oman had blogs of their own at the time. Chris Bertram is a philosopher at the University of Bristol in the United Kingdom—he had a blog called “Junius” and he later became a founding member of a widely read mostly academic group blog called “Crooked Timber.” I don’t remember exactly what Bertram said or why, but whatever it was, it made me think that what I was doing might be appreciated by thoughtful readers. Nate Oman recently became a law professor at the College of William and Mary in Virginia. At the time, Oman was a first year law student at Harvard with a blog called “A Good Oman,” and like Bertram, Oman provided thoughtful and appreciative feedback. Bertram and Oman opened my eyes to the blogosphere as a distinctive form of social and intellectual interaction—a space for communicating about serious ideas. Thanks guys. And then something else happened. I read an op/ed in the New York Times about a judicial nominee. The editorial focused on a case involving the application of the doctrine of res judicata (claim preclusion) to a case involving the tort of spoliation (destruction) of evidence. Well, I’ve written a treatise with a chapter on claim preclusion and another treatise with a chapter on the spoliation tort. So I read the case. And it struck me that the editorial was a hatchet job or incompetent or both. So I blogged about the editorial. And then the blogosphere took over—producing dozens and dozens of “links” to my post and thousands and thousands of “visits” to Legal Theory Blog. This really wasn’t the kind of attention I was looking for. I get no kicks from TV—especially being on it. But there was a lesson in my fifteen minutes of fame—an illustration of the awesome power of the Internet for rapid dissemination of information. Within a few weeks, Legal Theory Blog had hundreds of regular readers. When the readership began to climb into the thousands, I realized that an obsession with readership was adding to the not inconsiderable burden of getting out the blog on a daily basis. I stopped counting. I learned another lesson about the power of the blogosphere from a series of exchanges with Jack Balkin, who then ran Balkinization as a solo blog. In response to a column by Eddie Lazarus I posted a detailed reply, prompting Jack Balkin to publish a post entitled “Good Judging and ‘Following the Rules Laid Down.’” I countered with “A Neoformalist Manifesto,” followed by Balkin’s “Good Judging and "Following the Rules Laid Down," Part II.” The exchange ended with my “Fear and Loathing in New Haven.” The exchange conducted over the course of four days, runs almost fourteen-thousand words. Balkin’s contributions to the exchange were eloquent and powerful. They gave me the sense that the possibilities of blogging transcended the one-paragraph post; Balkin’s blogging blurred the lines between conventional legal scholarship and bloggership. Eventually, Legal Theory Blog evolved a fairly standard format. Lot’s of the content consists of links to new papers on SSRN and elsewhere. Every week, there is a “Download of the Week” which frequently ends with the tag line: download it while its hot! Another weekly feature is a book recommendation—called the “Legal Theory Bookworm.” Many law schools, post open-access versions of workshop papers on the web—Legal Theory Blog links to those in a weekly “Legal Theory Calendar,” which is reposted day-by-day, Monday through Friday. Once a week, I post an entry in the Legal Theory Lexicon, which covers topics like “The Coase Theorem,” “Ex Post and Ex Ante,” and so forth. If you scroll up, you'll find a link to the Webcast. Check it out! Webcast of Bloggership Conference I'm blogging from Austin Hall at Harvard Law School. Bloggership: How Blogs are Transforming Legal Scholarship has just started! The live webcase is available at this link. John Palfrey just finished the welcoming remarks and Paul Caron is now discussing "reverse triangular mergers." No really, but he was just kidding. I'll update this post from time to time today! My paper for the conference, Blogging and the Transformation of Legal Scholarship, can be downloaded from SSRN. All of the conference papers are available at this link! Blumensson on Vermeule & Sunstein on Life-Life Tradeoffs Eric Blumenson (Suffolk) has posted Killing in Good Conscience: Comments on Sunstein and Vermeule's Lesser Evil Argument for Capital Punishment and other Human Rights Violations on SSRN. Here is the Abstract:
Friday Calendar
University of Texas Law: Lisa Bressman, Vanderbilt University, "Inside the Administrative State: A Critical Look at the Practice of Presidential Control" Harvard, Berkman Center: Bloggership: How Blogs are Transforming Legal Scholarship
Kate Litvak (Texas): Law Prof Blogs: Useful, Yes; Scholarship, No
Georgetown Law & Economics: Randall Thomas, Vanderbilt University Law School University of San Diego: "The Rights and Wrongs of Discrimination."
Thursday, April 27, 2006
Meet the Bloggers in Tonight in Cambridge The Harvard Law School Berkman Center conference on blogging and legal scholarship will be this Friday, April 28. A whole bunch of us will be at the Zephyr Lounge in the Hyatt Regency Cambridge, 575 Memorial Drive from 9 pm or so to about 11 pm. If you are a reader of Legal Theory Blog and would like to join us, please do come by. So far, it looks like these bloggers are on for that evening: Douglas Berman, Sentencing Law and PolicySee you there! Thursday Calendar
University of Illinois Criminal Law Colloquium: Mariano-Florentino ("Tino") Cuéllar, Stanford University, The Political Economy of Preventive Criminal Enforcement Oxford Public International Law Discussion Group: Professor Alan Boyle, Some Reflections on the International Law-making Process Oxford Law Faculty, Invited Seminars in Constitutional Theory 2006: Adam Tomkins, speaking on The Republican Constitution with comments from Trevor Allan, Paul Craig and Timothy Endicott DePaul Law: Wendy Gordon, Boston University & the Hosier Distinguished Visiting IP Scholar, Copyright and Ethics: The Moral Duties of Copyright Owners Fordham Law: Martin S. Flaherty, Professor of Law and Co-Director, Joseph R. Crowley Program in International Human Rights University of Arizona Law: Kenji Yoshino, Yale Law School, "The New Equal Protection" Wednesday, April 26, 2006
Wednesday Calendar
USC-Caltech Center for the Study of Law & Politics: Elizabeth Garrett(USC Gould School of Law) and Mathew McCubbins (University of California, San Diego), "A Framework Law for Initiatives" Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law – Yeshiva University, Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program, Intellectual Property Speaker Series: Madhavi Sunder, University of California at Davis, I P3: The Convergence of Identity Politics, the Internet Protocol, and Intellectual Property Tuesday, April 25, 2006
Hasen on the Sixth Circuit on Hasen on Bush v. Gore and the Theory of Horizontal Stare Decisis
This debate raises some very interesting issues of constitutional theory--about the fundamental nature of constitutional stare decisis in two dimensions: (1) vertical, from the Supreme Court to the lower federal courts, and (2) horizontal, from the past of the Supreme Court to its future. With respect to horizontal stare decisis in the Supreme Court, the conventional view is that the Supreme Court should afford its own prior decisions a presumption of validity. What does that mean? One possibility would be that this “presumption” is a mere “bursting bubble.” Precedents will be followed until and unless there are good reasons to depart from them. If this were the only role for precedent, then it would be virtually no role at all—it takes only a slender needle of flimsy argument to burst a bubble. Likewise, the presumption view is virtually meaningless if it only decides cases in which the arguments for and against sticking with the precedent are in equipoise. Of course, there will be some cases in which the arguments for and against a change in the law are perfectly balanced, but such cases are likely to be rare. The presumption view of the force of precedent is implausible. A more reasonable view is that precedents are entitled to weight because of the costs of legal change. One such cost is associated with reliance and expectations. Individuals and institutions may fail to receive expected benefits or incur avoidable costs. Another set of costs may be related to the implementation of new legal rules—at a minimum, the treatises will need to be rewritten. The instrumentalist view of precedent conceives of the decision whether to overrule existing precedent as simply adding another factor to the balance of factors that are relevant to the selection of an optimal rule. From the realist perspective, precedents should be overrule when the benefits of overruling exceed the costs and precedents should be followed when they already provide the optimal rule or when the costs of changing the law are greater than the marginal benefits the better rule would provide. The instrumentalist view of precedent is peculiar, because it denies that Supreme Court precedents should be treated as legally authoritative by the Supreme Court itself. One way of drawing out this peculiarity is by comparing the situation in which there is a prior Supreme Court precedent on a particular point of law to the situation in which there is no prior decision and a new case presents a novel issue of law. Of course, it is possible that the former case involves greater reliance interests than the later case, but this is not necessarily so. It might well be that the relevant individuals and institutions have made plans based on guesses about the Supreme Court’s likely decision or that they have made plans for no good reason at all. From the instrumentalist perspective, reliance interests are valued in terms of consequences of disappointed expectations. Stare decisis is simply one mechanism by which reliance interests could be generated. The point is that the instrumentalist conception reduces the force of precedent to a contingent policy concern—one that may drop out entirely in some cases. What is the alternative? The formalist conception of stare decisis is based on the idea that precedents are legally binding or authoritative. That is, a formalist believes that precedents provide what are sometimes called “content independent” or “peremptory” reasons for action. Of course, the formalist conception of precedents as legally binding is quite familiar, even in our realist legal culture. When it comes to vertical stare decisis, the conventional notion is that the decisions of higher courts are binding on lower courts. A Court of Appeals may not decide to overrule a Supreme Court decision because the advantages of the better rule outweigh the costs of changing legal rules. The idea of binding precedent also operates at the level of intermediate appellate courts. Three judge panels of the United States Courts of Appeal are bound by the prior decisions of the Court; they are not free to decide that the benefits of a better rule outweigh the benefits of adhering to the law of the circuit. There is a second contrast between realist and formalist conceptions of precedent. Realist courts are inclined to view their power as legislative in nature. This is clearest in the case of courts of last resort, as is the Supreme Court of the United States in constitutional cases. This leads to the emergence of what might be called the legislative holding—in which the Opinion of the Court includes a phrase that may begin, “We hold that . . .” and then states a broad rule that decides the case at hand but may go far beyond its facts. Lower courts may be inclined to treat legislative holdings as authoritative. For one thing, courts of last resort have a power that real legislatures lack; they can actually intervene in particular cases and address direct orders to the lower courts—powers that legislatures lack. Legislative holdings blur the familiar distinction between dictum and holding. From a realist perspective, a firm statement of the rule joined by a clear majority may constitute good evidence of the court’s future actions—even if the statement is unnecessary to the resolution of the dispute at hand. Even formalists may be tempted by the practice of legislative holdings-—after all, they do facilitate predictability and certainty about the content of the law. There are, however, formalist reasons for adhering to the traditional view of stare decisis—-that opinions are binding only insofar as they decide the case before the court. This is the traditional theory of the ration decidendi—“the reason for the decision” which is limited by the legally salient facts of the case that is decided. Given this traditional view, case law is slow moving. It takes many decisions to create a general rule, and many more to change one. Given the realist practice of “legislative holdings,” a single case could create a right to abortion with an elaborate three trimester scheme. And a single case could abolish that right. Given the formalist alternative, a right to abortion could only have been created through many decisions; once established, it would take many many more to modify or extinguish that right. The two distinguishing features of the realist idea of precedent work in tandem. When legal rules are emerging, they are built slowly, piece by piece. Once established by a body of precedent, a legal rule can only change slowly. Each alteration must be consistent with the binding force of prior decisions. New cases can only move the law by small steps, whose limits are demarcated by the facts which define ratio decidendi of the new case. Working in tandem, these two features of the neoformalist doctrine of precedent operate to create predictability, certainty, and stability in the law—not by declaring broad rules in single cases but through the accumulated decisions of many cases over time. So how does all of this apply to Bush v. Gore and Hasen's view that the decision is likely to be confined to its facts? I think it exposes a certain tension or contradiction within the prevailing legal conception of constitutional stare decisis. On the one hand, the doctrine of vertical stare decisis is formalist: Supreme Court decisions are binding on the lower courts. On the other hand, horizontal stare decisis within the Supreme Court is realist--the court does not consider itself bound by its own prior decisions and yet feels free to issue legislative holdings that purport to establish binding rules. This puts lower courts in a bit of a bind. On the one hand, they are required to follow Bush v. Gore, to treat it as a binding decision of the Supreme Court. On the other hand, the lower courts know that Bush v. Gore may not be treated as a binding decision by the Supreme Court itself and hence that (in some sense) the decision does not make law except in the narrow sense of "law of the case" on remand. So what the lower courts to do? Either they ignore Bush v. Gore in contravention of their duty to treat Supreme Court decisions as binding, or they follow it, and make decisions that in reality will be out of sync with the law in some larger and more realistic sense. To me, it is not surprising that the Sixth Circuit panel was split and that the disagreement was heated. That's simply a symptom of corrupting influence of realism on the Supreme Court's doctrine of horizontal stare decisis Read Hasen's fine post Conference Announcement: The Future of Legal Education at Vanderbilt
Tuesday Calendar
Ed Glaeser, Fred and Eleanor Glimp Professor of Economics, Harvard University, Why Does Democracy Need Education? Oxford Internet Institute: Jonathan Zittrain: Internet Governance and Regulation: the Future of the Internet--and How to Stop it Chicago IP Colloquium, Loyola University Chicago School of Law: Professor Sonia Kaytal, Fordham University School of Law, Trademark Intersectionality Georgetown Law: Lama Abu-Odeh Georgetown Constitutonal Law & Theory: Rick Garnett (Law, Notre Dame), Religious Freedom, Church Autonomy, and the Libertas Ecclesiae Perry on the Role of the Supreme Court in Protecting Human Rights Michael Perry (Emory) has posted PROTECTING CONSTITUTIONALLY ENTRENCHED HUMAN RIGHTS: WHAT ROLE SHOULD THE SUPREME COURT PLAY? (WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO CAPITAL PUNISHMENT, ABORTION, AND SAME-SEX UNIONS) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Hathaway & Lavinbuk on Goldsmith & Posner on Internatonal Law Oona Hathaway & Ariel Lavinbuk have posted Rationalism and Revisionism in International Law (Harvard Law Review, Vol. 119, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Conference Announcement: Joint Session 2006 at Southampton
Monday, April 24, 2006
Weekend Update On Saturday, the Download of the Week was The Poverty of the Moral Stimulus by John Mikhail abd the Legal Theory Bookworm recommended Cardozo's The Nature of the Judicial Process. On Sunday, the Legal Theory Lexicon entry was Indeterminacy and the Legal Theory Calendar rounded up this week's conference, talks, and workshops. Speaking of the Calendar, I'll be at the Bloggership conference Harvard on Friday. My paper Blogging and the Transformation of Legal Scholarship is available from SSRN. You can find all the confernce papers here. And the weekend also saw an update of the Entry Level Hiring Report. Things are starting to wind down--Harvard, Columbia, and a few other places still have offers out. I am still taking reports and rumours. Email information to: lsolum@gmail.com. Monday Calendar
University of Texas Law: Jeffrey Segal (Stony Brook) "Changing Dynamics of Senate Voting on Supreme Court Nominees" Segal does very important work on judicial attitudes and behavior. Emory Law: Rachel Moran, Boalt Hall, "Grutter v. Bollinger: The Heirs of Brown." Yale Workplace Theory & Practice: Katie Quan, Institute of Industrial Relations, University of California at Berkeley, Women Crossing Borders to Organize UCLA Law: Prof. Mark Grady, UCLA School of Law, "Chimpanzee Autarky: Using Chimpanzee Norms to Explain Chimpanzee Behavior" Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program: International Intellectual Property — A Roundtable on Current Developments Professors Katsuya Tamai (U Tokyo), Coenraad Visser (U South Africa), Susy Frankel (Victoria U of Wellington) Georgetown Law & Philosophy: Martha Nussbaum (Law and Philosophy, University of Chicago) Columbia Law & Economics: Daniel M. Klerman, University of Southern California Law School, Jurisdictional Competition and the Evolution of the Common Law Yeazell on Shutts Stephen C. Yeazell (University of California, Los Angeles - School of Law) has posted Overhearing Part of a Conversation: Shutts as a Moment in a Long Dialogue on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Krinsky on State Decisis & Deference in Patent Claim Construction David Krinsky (Law Clerk - US District Court for the District of Maryland) has posted The Supreme Court, Stare Decisis, and the Role of Judicial Deference in Patent Claim Construction Appeals (Maryland Law Review, Vol. 66, 2006 Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Greenberg on Gender Nonconformity Discrimination Julie A. Greenberg (Thomas Jefferson School of Law) has posted What do Scalia and Thomas Really Think About Sex? Title VII and Gender Nonconformity Discrimination: Protection for Transsexuals, Intersexuals, Gays and Lesbians (Thomas Jefferson Law Review, Vol. 24, p. 149, 2002) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sunday, April 23, 2006
Check it Out I've had a frantically busy semester--the busiest of my entire career--so, I'm sure I'm the very last person in the universe to discover Law and Letters. Lot's of really marvelous stuff, including More Late Night Thoughts On Duncan Kennedy and Blogging. Legal Theory Calendar
University of Texas Law: Jeffrey Segal (Stony Brook) "Changing Dynamics of Senate Voting on Supreme Court Nominees" Emory Law: Rachel Moran, Boalt Hall, "Grutter v. Bollinger: The Heirs of Brown." Yale Workplace Theory & Practice: Katie Quan, Institute of Industrial Relations, University of California at Berkeley, Women Crossing Borders to Organize UCLA Law: Prof. Mark Grady, UCLA School of Law, "Chimpanzee Autarky: Using Chimpanzee Norms to Explain Chimpanzee Behavior" Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program: International Intellectual Property — A Roundtable on Current Developments Professors Katsuya Tamai (U Tokyo), Coenraad Visser (U South Africa), Susy Frankel (Victoria U of Wellington) Georgetown Law & Philosophy: Martha Nussbaum (Law and Philosophy, University of Chicago) Columbia Law & Economics: Daniel M. Klerman, University of Southern California Law School, Jurisdictional Competition and the Evolution of the Common Law
Ed Glaeser, Fred and Eleanor Glimp Professor of Economics, Harvard University, Why Does Democracy Need Education? Oxford Internet Institute: Jonathan Zittrain: Internet Governance and Regulation: the Future of the Internet--and How to Stop it Chicago IP Colloquium, Loyola University Chicago School of Law: Professor Sonia Kaytal, Fordham University School of Law, Trademark Intersectionality Georgetown Law: Lama Abu-Odeh Georgetown Constitutonal Law & Theory: Rick Garnett (Law, Notre Dame), Religious Freedom, Church Autonomy, and the Libertas Ecclesiae
USC-Caltech Center for the Study of Law & Politics: Elizabeth Garrett(USC Gould School of Law) and Mathew McCubbins (University of California, San Diego), "A Framework Law for Initiatives" Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law – Yeshiva University, Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program, Intellectual Property Speaker Series: Madhavi Sunder, University of California at Davis, I P3: The Convergence of Identity Politics, the Internet Protocol, and Intellectual Property
University of Illinois Criminal Law Colloquium: Mariano-Florentino ("Tino") Cuéllar, Stanford University, The Political Economy of Preventive Criminal Enforcement Oxford Public International Law Discussion Group: Professor Alan Boyle, Some Reflections on the International Law-making Process Oxford Law Faculty, Invited Seminars in Constitutional Theory 2006: Adam Tomkins, speaking on The Republican Constitution with comments from Trevor Allan, Paul Craig and Timothy Endicott DePaul Law: Wendy Gordon, Boston University & the Hosier Distinguished Visiting IP Scholar, Copyright and Ethics: The Moral Duties of Copyright Owners Fordham Law: Martin S. Flaherty, Professor of Law and Co-Director, Joseph R. Crowley Program in International Human Rights University of Arizona Law: Kenji Yoshino, Yale Law School, "The New Equal Protection"
University of Texas Law: Lisa Bressman, Vanderbilt University, "Inside the Administrative State: A Critical Look at the Practice of Presidential Control" Harvard, Berkman Center: Bloggership: How Blogs are Transforming Legal Scholarship
Kate Litvak (Texas): Law Prof Blogs: Useful, Yes; Scholarship, No
Georgetown Law & Economics: Randall Thomas, Vanderbilt University Law School University of San Diego: "The Rights and Wrongs of Discrimination."
Legal Theory Lexicon: Indeterminacy
The Indeterminacy Debate The indeterminacy thesis is associated with legal realism, but in its most extreme form, it is most strongly identified with the Critical Legal Studies movement--a loose and multifaceted cluster of legal scholars that became very prominent in the 1980s. The indeterminacy debate is about the claim that the law does not constrain judicial decisions. Put differently, the claim is that all cases are hard cases and that there are no easy cases. The strongest version of the claim is the notion that any result in any legal dispute can be justified as the legally correct outcome, but the thesis can be modified or weakened in various ways. What does the indeterminacy thesis mean? Let's call the claim that the laws (broadly defined to include cases, regulations, statutes, constitutional provisions, and other legal materials) do not determine legal outcomes the indeterminacy thesis. Because there are many different versions of the indeterminacy thesis, our approach will be to identify clearly the distinct versions of the indeterminacy thesis and then to consider each version of the thesis on its own merits. Indeterminacy versus Underdeterminacy The next step in clarifying the indeterminacy debate is to distinguish between "indeterminacy" and "underdeterminacy" of law. Thus far, we have accepted the implicit assumption that indeterminacy and determinacy are exhaustive categories, i.e. that the decision of a case is either determined by the law or it is indeterminate. This assumption is not correct. A legal dispute may be constrained by the law, but not determined by it. Roughly, an case is underdetermined by the law if the outcome (including the formal mandate and the content of the opinion) can vary within limits that are defined by the legal materials. This approximation can be made more precise by considering the relationship between two sets of outcomes of a given case. The first set consists of all possible results — all the imaginable variations in the mandate (affirmance, reversal, remand, etc.) and in the reasoning of the opinion. The second set consists of the outcomes that can be squared with the law — the set or legally acceptable outcomes. The distinctions between indeterminacy, underdeterminacy and determinacy of the law with respect to a given case may be marked with the following definitions: Is the law radically indeterminate? The strongest (the most ambitious) claim about the indeterminacy of law is the claim that in every possible case, any possible outcome is legally correct. In other words, the strong indeterminacy thesis is the claim that the law is radically indeterminate:
The Argument from Easy Cases One way to establish that there is at least one possible case in which at least one outcome is legally incorrect has been called "the argument from easy cases" by Fred Schauer. In its simplest form, the argument from easy cases points to a hypothetical case in which at least one outcome is legally incorrect. The following discussion attempts to formulate one such easy case:
Changing the Hypothetical Of course, we can easily change the hypothetical so that the legally correct outcome would change. Just add a conspiratorial conversation at the beach that does violate the Sherman Act. But the fact that the hypothetical can be changed so as to change the legally correct outcome is not responsive to the argument from easy cases. Let us stipulate for the sake of argument that it is always be possible to add facts to an easy case such that the addition of the new facts will change the legally correct outcome of the case. This does not demonstrate that there are no easy cases. Quite the contrary, the fact that the advocate of the strong indeterminacy thesis needed to add facts to the easy case in order to change the legally correct outcome shows that as originally stated the easy case was not indeterminate. If the strong indeterminacy thesis were true, then a reasonable legal argument should be available on the facts as originally stated in the hypothetical. The additional facts should not be necessary. That facts must be added to transform an easy case into a hard one demonstrates that the law does constrain the set of legally correct outcomes. Is a modest version of the indeterminacy thesis defensible? If the strong indeterminacy thesis cannot be supported, is there a more modest claim about indeterminacy that is defensible and has critical bite? One modest version of the indeterminacy thesis might be the following: in most (or almost all) of the cases that are actually litigated, the outcome is underdetermined by the law. This claim about indeterminacy is not refuted by the argument from hypothetical easy cases. Confirmation of the actually-litigated underdeterminacy thesis would require empirical investigation, but there are some good reasons to believe that cases which actually proceed to filing, trial, or appeal will frequently be underdetermined by the law. Litigants will rarely have an incentive to settle easy cases. For example, in a civil dispute where the law gives a determinate answer to the question of who will win and what the amount of their judgment will be, the parties to litigation will usually prefer to settle, rather than incur the expenses of litigation. Uncertainty about the law is one of the factors that selects which cases will be filed, go to trial, and be appealed. This point should not be exaggerated, however: litigation may proceed for any number of reasons, including an irrational overconfidence in a hopeless case, uncertainty about facts in a case in which the law is clear, and so forth. Important Cases Another modest version of the indeterminacy thesis claims that while many ordinary cases are roughly determinate, all the really important cases are indeterminate. Put more precisely, the claim might be that the important issues in important cases are underdetermined by the law. If true, this claim might preserve almost all of the critical force of the strong indeterminacy thesis. Yes, there are easy cases, but those cases are unimportant. One difficulty with the important case version of the indeterminacy thesis is its potential circularity. Our concept of what counts as an important case may have indeterminacy as a component. Part of what makes a case important is that the result is not certain or predictable; if we all knew how the case would come out, we would not be interested. Likewise, the Supreme Court may select cases in part on the basis of their legal indeterminacy. Conclusion I have just begun to scratch the surface of the indeterminacy debate, but I hope that I've provided enough perspective so that you can begin to think about this important question on your own. As I'm sure you know by now, I am not a fan of the radical indeterminacy thesis, but I also think it is important to recognize that the law is underdeterminate in important ways. For more on the indeterminacy debate, see Lawrence On the Indeterminacy Crisis: Critiquing Critical Dogma, 54 University of Chicago Law Review 462 (1987). (online here) Saturday, April 22, 2006
Legal Theory Bookworm The Legal Theory Bookworm's selection is a modern classic--The Nature of the Judicial Process by Benjamin Cardozo. Cardozo's short book provides a marvelous introduction to the law from an early realist perspective. Highly recommended! Download of the Week The Download of the Week is The Poverty of the Moral Stimulus by John Mikhail. Here is the abstract:
Friday, April 21, 2006
Welcome to the Blogosophere . . . . . . to Colin Farrelly's In Search of Englightment, which has the great subtitle:
Alford on Solum on Blogging & Legal Scholarship Check out Solum on Blogging and Legal Scholarship by Roger Alford on Opinio Juris. Read the whole thing, but I want to respond to the following point in particular:
Solum on Blogging and Legal Scholarship I've posted Blogging and the Transformation of Legal Scholarship on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Friday Calendar
Villanova Law: Christopher Drahozhol, University of Kansas School of Law University of Texas Law: Cindy Estlund (Columbia University) University of Georgia International Law: Ed Swaine (University of Pennsylvania, Wharton School), "Judicial States" University of Georgia Law: Thomas Lee (Fordham), Federal Court Review of Federal Law Voluntarily Incorporated into State Law UCLA Law: Devon Carbado, UCLA School of Law Ohio State Legal History: Thomas D. Morris, Norms and Facts: Racially Mixed Juries in Reconstruction South Carolina Notre Dame Law: Professor Heather Gerken, Harvard Law School Yale Information Society Project: Access to Knowledge (A2K) Conference Georgetown Law & Economics: Michael Trebilcock, University of Toronto Law School Thursday, April 20, 2006
Wright on Slotting Josh Wright (George Mason) has posted Slotting Contracts and Consumer Welfare on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Duncan on Establishment and Subsidiarity Kyle Duncan (University of Mississippi College of Law) has posted Subsidiarity and Religious Establishments in the U.S. Constitution on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Mikhail on the Poverty of Moral Stimulus John Mikhail (Georgetown) has posted The Poverty of the Moral Stimulus on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Thursday Calendar
Yale Legal Theory: Robin West, Georgetown (Law), Unenumerated Duties William Mitchell Law Review Symposium: 8 Cases You Need to Know University of North Dakota Indian Law: Rebecca Tsosie, "Native Peoples and Reparations: Toward a Vision of Justice and Reconciliation" UCLA Tax Policy & Public Finance: Joel Slemrod, University of Michigan, Ross School of Business, Professor of Business Economics and Public Policy, Taxation and Big Brother: Information, Personalization, and Privacy in 21st Century Tax Policy UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: David A. Strauss, University of Chicago Stanford Law & Economics: Howard Chang (University of Pennsylvania Law School), "Cultural Communities in a Global Labor Market: Immigration Restrictions as Residential Segregation" NYU Tax: Jeffrey Liebman, Harvard University, Kennedy School of Government UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Ruth Chang, Philosophy Rutgers University, PERSONAL AND IMPERSONAL REASONS Fordham Law: Fordham Annual Conference on Intellectual Property Law and Policy George Mason Law: Dean Williamson, U.S. Department of Justice; Title: Organization, Control and the Single Entity Defense in Antitrust Wednesday, April 19, 2006
Second Annual Conglomerate Junior Scholars Workshop Check out The Second Annual Conglomerate Junior Scholars Workshop at Conglomare. Here's a taste:
Citations to Blogs in Law Review Articles Check out A Collection of Law Review Articles Citing Legal Blogs by Ian Best in 3L Epiphany. Here's a taste:
Claeys on Coase and Natural Property Rights Eric Claeys (Saint Louis University - School of Law) has posted Jefferson Meets Coase: Train Sparks, the Harm-Benefit Distinction, and Natural Property Rights on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Wednesday Calendar
NYU Legal History: Rebecca Rix, Golieb Fellow, NYU School of Law, "Policing the General Welfare in Post-World War I Progressive Reconstitution" Emory Law: Owen Jones, Vanderbilt Law School, "Evolutionary Analysis and the Endowment Effect: An Empirical Investigation." Call for Papers: Metaphysics 2006
Tuesday, April 18, 2006
Entry-Level Hiring Rumors Can someone help with the following?
Tuesday Calendar
Northwestern Constitutional Law & Theory: Martha Nussbaum, University of Chicago, "The Fixed Star" Chapter 2 & Chapter 3 Lewis & Clark: Joseph Miller Ordinary Artisans' Ordinary Inventions: Toward Reality-Based Patent Law Georgetown Law: Bob Pitofsky Georgetown Constitutional Law & Theory: Tom Ginsburg (law and political science, Illinois) Monday, April 17, 2006
Law & Solum on the Nuclear Option David Law and I have posted a substantially revised version of our paper on the politics of the "nuclear option" and judicial selection, Judicial Selection, Appointments Gridlock, and the Nuclear Option, on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Garnett on Politics & Religion Rick Garnett has an op/ed entitled Campaigning from the pulpit: Why not?, over at USA Today. Here's a taste:
Monday Calendar
Update: Emory Law: Bill Buzbee, Emory School of Law, "Westway, the City, and the Law." University of Cincinnati Law: Prof. William Henderson, Indiana (Bloomington) University School of Law, “The Changing Economic Geography of the Am Law 200" Yale Workplace Theory & Policy: ROLAND FRYER, Economics, Harvard University, The Simple Economics of Affirmative Action University of Texas Law: Jens Dammann (UT), Extraterritorial Courts for Corporate Law University of Alabama Law: Roland Mitchell, LSU School of Education NYU Law: Geoff Miller Marquette Law: Dan Capra, Fordham Law School, The Relationship Between Supreme Court Decision Making and Federal Evidence Rulemaking: Crawford and Other Interruptions Hofstra Law: Barton Beebe, Cardozo Law School, “An Empirical Analysis of the Multifactor Tests for Trademark Infringement” Columbia Law & Economics: Jack Goldsmith of Harvard Law School, "Democracy, Prudence, Intervention" Sunday, April 16, 2006
Cases Citing Blogs Over at 3L Epiphany, check out Cases Citing Legal Blogs, including a cite to the Legal Theory Lexicon. Legal Theory Calendar
Yale Workplace Theory & Policy: ROLAND FRYER, Economics, Harvard University, The Simple Economics of Affirmative Action University of Texas Law: Jens Dammann (UT), Extraterritorial Courts for Corporate Law University of Alabama Law: Roland Mitchell, LSU School of Education NYU Law: Geoff Miller Marquette Law: Dan Capra, Fordham Law School, The Relationship Between Supreme Court Decision Making and Federal Evidence Rulemaking: Crawford and Other Interruptions Hofstra Law: Barton Beebe, Cardozo Law School, “An Empirical Analysis of the Multifactor Tests for Trademark Infringement” Georgetown Law & Philosophy: Nancy Sherman (Philosophy, Georgetown) Columbia Law & Economics: Jack Goldsmith of Harvard Law School, "Democracy, Prudence, Intervention"
Northwestern Constitutional Law & Theory: Martha Nussbaum, University of Chicago, "The Fixed Star" Chapter 2 & Chapter 3 Lewis & Clark: Joseph Miller Ordinary Artisans' Ordinary Inventions: Toward Reality-Based Patent Law Georgetown Law: Bob Pitofsky Georgetown Constitutional Law & Theory: Tom Ginsburg (law and political science, Illinois)
NYU Legal History: Rebecca Rix, Golieb Fellow, NYU School of Law, "Policing the General Welfare in Post-World War I Progressive Reconstitution" Emory Law: Owen Jones, Vanderbilt Law School, "Evolutionary Analysis and the Endowment Effect: An Empirical Investigation."
Yale Legal Theory: Robin West, Georgetown (Law), Unenumerated Duties William Mitchell Law Review Symposium: 8 Cases You Need to Know University of North Dakota Indian Law: Rebecca Tsosie, "Native Peoples and Reparations: Toward a Vision of Justice and Reconciliation" UCLA Tax Policy & Public Finance: Joel Slemrod, University of Michigan, Ross School of Business, Professor of Business Economics and Public Policy, Taxation and Big Brother: Information, Personalization, and Privacy in 21st Century Tax Policy UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: David A. Strauss, University of Chicago Stanford Law & Economics: Howard Chang (University of Pennsylvania Law School), "Cultural Communities in a Global Labor Market: Immigration Restrictions as Residential Segregation" NYU Tax: Jeffrey Liebman, Harvard University, Kennedy School of Government UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Ruth Chang, Philosophy Rutgers University, PERSONAL AND IMPERSONAL REASONS Fordham Law: Fordham Annual Conference on Intellectual Property Law and Policy George Mason Law: Dean Williamson, U.S. Department of Justice; Title: Organization, Control and the Single Entity Defense in Antitrust
University of Texas Law: Cindy Estlund (Columbia University) University of Georgia International Law: Ed Swaine (University of Pennsylvania, Wharton School), "Judicial States" University of Georgia Law: Thomas Lee (Fordham), Federal Court Review of Federal Law Voluntarily Incorporated into State Law UCLA Law: Devon Carbado, UCLA School of Law Ohio State Legal History: Thomas D. Morris, Norms and Facts: Racially Mixed Juries in Reconstruction South Carolina Notre Dame Law: Professor Heather Gerken, Harvard Law School Yale Information Society Project: Access to Knowledge (A2K) Conference Georgetown Law & Economics: Michael Trebilcock, University of Toronto Law School Legal Theory Lexicon: Strict Construction & Judicial Activism
Strict Construction Strict construction is short hand for the idea that the United States Constitution should be strictly construed. The phrase appears to have become popular as a campaign slogan used by Richard Nixon when he ran for President in 1968. Nixon promised that he would appoint judges who were "strict constructionists" as opposed to the "judicial activism" that characterized the Warren Court, but the phrase has much earlier origins and may go back as far as the late eighteenth century. The question is: what does strict construction mean? Is there really a method of constitutional interpretation described by the phrase "strict construction" or is this a mere political slogan? The confusion engendered by the term is illustrated by the following definition (offered on law.com):
Judicial Activism In conservative political discourse in the United States, "strict construction" is good and "judicial activism" is bad. But what is judicial activism? Once again, it is not clear that this phrase has any real meaning. The standard argument against the use of the term "judicial activism" is that it translates best as "judicial decision making with which I disagree." To see why this is so, once again let us consider the possible interpretations of the phrase: Conclusion This post has had two goals. The first is to convince you that "strict construction" and "judicial activism" are simply not very useful as theory terms for academic constitutional lawyers. The second is to illustrate the importance of clear explication of constitutional concepts. Constitutional theory is a value-laden activity. Debates about positions in constitutional theory are frequently extensions of debates in moral and political theory generally. For that reason, it is very important for constitutional theorists to be very careful about their use of language. Links Chad Oldfather, Defining Judicial Inactivism: Models of Adjudication and the Duty to Decide Saturday, April 15, 2006
Legal Theory Bookworm "Intuitions" play a major role in normative legal theory--especially in conjunction with a method of argumentation that borrows from John Rawls's idea of "reflective equilibrium. But most legal theorists have never thought in a systematic way about ethical intuitionism--the view in moral philosophy and metaethics that systematizes the role of intuitions in normative theory. This week's recommendation from the Legal Theory Bookworm is The Good in the Right : A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value by Robert Audi. Here's a description:
Download of the Week The Download of the Week is How to Remove a Federal Judge by Steve Smith and Sai Prakash (University of San Diego). Here is the abstract:
Friday, April 14, 2006
Sinden on the Tragedy of the Commons Amy Sinden (Temple University - James E. Beasley School of Law) has posted The Tragedy of the Commons and the Myth of a Private Property Solution on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sinden's article is certainly very interesting. I would offer the following observation. One key to the "how much" question is information. In partiucular, there are two information problems that must be solved to provide optimal levels of pollution control. The first information problem concerns the costs of pollution abatement: polluters can acquire this information at a far lower cost than can government--because polluters know how their operations work and what secondary economic effects a particular abatement technology or practice might produce. The second information problem concerns the environmental costs imposed by pollution. This problem is very serious--because the individuals and firms who bear these costs are frequently unaware of both the damage and the causal pathways that produce it. The costs of acquiring this information are very high, and for that reason, private law solutions are problematic. (It would cost me more to acquire information about damage to my health from air pollution than I would realize from a tort action, even if litigation costs approached zero.) One way to in which the market can answer the "how much" question is for government to impose a pollution tax that equals the social costs imposed by the pollution. This requires further information--about how much pollution each source generates, but that information is required by any regime of pollution control. But there are problems with this solution--including the public choice problems (lobbying to reduce the tax below the true social costs) and the problem of insuring adequate levels of investment in the creation of the information about social costs necessary to set the tax accurately. But if the tax were set an accurate level, the market would then determine how much pollution each source would generate. The external diseconomies would be internalized. At any rate, that's how I thought about this problem when I was 16. Since then, my interests have shifted, but I still think about this problem from time to time. I now think that a better market-based solution would solve the second information problem differently. The source of the problem is the disaggregation of private rights to damages caused by pollution. In a sense, it is an anticommons problem--the rights are too fragmented to provide adequate incentives and cooperation involves too many transaction costs. The solution is to provide a mechanism for the aggregation of the fragmented rights. My off-the-cuff version of this is the creation of an "adverse possession" mechanism. Private actors--likely NGOs such as the NRDC or FOE--would have stake a claim to the "choses-in-action" of well-defined classes of persons, firms, and public entitites that suffered pollution damage. Such a class might be defined as: "All persons and property owners within a 30 mile radius of the Acme Company factory." If the owners of the rights did not file their own lawsuit within a specified period after the claim was filed, the adverse possessor would then acquire the rights and could prosecute the lawsuit, now as the owner of the rights that formerly belonged to the class. (These rights should be tradeable for obvious reasons; multiple claimant problems have various solutions, including the familiar "first in time" solution.) The adverse-possession solution allows private actors to internalize the benefits of producing the information necessary for the tort action to succeed. The defendant will then also have an incentive to produce information whenever there is reason to believe that the information produced by the plaintiff/adverse-possessor over estimates the social costs. This eliminates the public choice and underinvestment-in-information problems created by pollution taxes. Well, enough of that. I certainly recommend Sinden's paper. Download it while its hot! Friday Calendar
University of Georgia Interntional Law: Roger Alford (Pepperdine), Foreign Relations as a Matter of Interpretation: The Use and Abuse of Charming Betsy UCLA Law: Scott L. Cummings, Acting Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law, "Transnational Public Interest Law" Thursday, April 13, 2006
Thursday Calendar
Yale Law, Economics & Organizations: Professor Alison Morantz, Stanford, Law, Post-Accident Drug Testing & Workers' Compensation Claims in a Fortune 500 Company University of Illinois Criminal Law Colloquium, Susan Klein, University of Texas, Enhancing the Judicial Role in Criminal Plea and Sentence Bargaining University of North Dakota Indian Law: Erma J. Vizenor, "Tribal Sovereignty, the Federal Trust Responsibility, and Constitutional Reform" University of Michigan Law & Economics: Daniel Gervais, Ottawa, Intellectual Property and Development: Towards a Strategy UCLA Tax Policy & Public Finance: Dennis Ventry, Visiting Scholar in Taxation, UCLA School of Law, Suspicious Minds: The Uneasy Relationship Between Tax Lawyers and the IRS UCLA Law: Fernando Rámon Vegas Torrealba, Venezuelan Supreme Court Justice, "Democracy in Venezuela under the 1999 Bolivarian Constitution" Northwestern Tax: Lee Ann Fennell, Associate Professor, University of Illinois College of Law, "Taxation Over Time" NYU Tax: Mitchell Kane, University of Virginia Law School, "Risk and Redistribution in Open and Closed Economies." George Mason Law: Iliana Ilieva, GMU School of Law Levy Fellow Florida State Law: Barbara Fried, Stanford Law School, Contractarianism as the Site of Justice Yin on Terrorism Prosecutions & Coercion Tung Yin (University of Iowa, College of Law) has posted Coercion and Terrorism Prosecutions in the Shadow of Military Detention (Brigham Young University Law Review, November 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Corrado on Addiction & Action Michael L. Corrado (University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill - School of Law) has posted Addiction and the Theory of Action on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sandefur on Kelo Timothy Sandefur (Pacific Legal Foundation - Economic Liberties Project) has posted The 'Backlash' So Far: Will Citizens Get Meaningful Eminent Domain Reform? on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Conference Announcement: Altruism & Moral Psychology at Sheffield
Wednesday, April 12, 2006
Prakash on Removal & Tenure in Office Sai Prakash (University of San Diego) has posted Removal and Tenure in Office on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Wednesday Calendar
University of Georgia Law: Alan Watson (UGA), Lord Mansfield: Judicial Integrity or its Lack: Somerset's Case NYU Legal History: Alison LaCroix, Golieb Fellow, NYU School of Law, "Drawing the Line: The Pre-Revolutionary Origins of Federal Ideas of Sovereignty." Tuesday, April 11, 2006
Tuesday Calendar
University of Pennsylvania Tax Policy: Mitchell Kane University of Oxford-University of Texas Law Faculty Interchange
Ms. Mindy Chen-Wishart, Fellow in Law - Merton College, Oxford; University Lecturer and Director of Undergraduate Studies, Law Faculty - University of Oxford, "Undue Influence: Vindicating Relationships of Influence", Discussant: Professor Mark Gergen, UT School of Law Dr. Wanjiru Njoya, Fellow in Law - St. John's College, Oxford, "Employee Participation in Corporate Governance: the End, the Beginning of the End, or Perhaps the End of the Beginning?", Discussant: Professor Jens Dammann, UT School of Law Ms. Sandra Meredith, IT Training & Development Officer - Bodleian Law Library; Law Faculty - Oxford University, "The Oxford Law Legal Research Skills Programme", Discussant: Ms. Jeanne Price, Tarlton Law Library Dr. Katja Ziegler, Lecturer in Law, Fellow and Deputy Director of the Institute of European and Comparative Law - University of Oxford, "The Constitutionalisation of the British Constitution?: Recent Aspects of Constitutional Change in the UK Through 'the Two Europes' - Towards a Judicial Review of Statutes?", Discussant: Professor Ernie Young, UT School of Law Mr. Nicholas Bamforth, Fellow in Law - The Queen's College, Oxford; University Lecturer in Law - University of Oxford, "The Constitutional Status and Impact of the [UK] Human Rights Act 1998", Discussant: Professor H.W. Perry Jr., UT School of Law; Government Department Georgetown Law: Julie Cohen Georgetown Constitutional Law & Theory: Ted Ruger (law, Pennsylvania), The Chief Justice's Special Authority and the Norms of Judicial Power Lipshaw on Business Ethics Jeff Lipshaw has posted Law as Rationalization: Getting Beyond Reason to Business Ethics on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Conference Announcement: Bloggership at Harvard's Berkman Center
Monday, April 10, 2006
Monday Calendar
University of Texas Law: Stefanie Lindquist (Vanderbilt), "Judicial Review by the Burger and Rehnquist Courts: Explaining Justices' Responses to Constitutional Challenges" UCLA Law: Professor Jerry Kang and Professor Gary Blasi, UCLA School of Law, "Behavioral Realism in Law: Implicit Cognition & Social Justice" NYU Law: Lily Batchelder Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program: Srividhya Ragavan, University of Oklahoma, Replacing Sticks with Carrots: Is the Enforcement Mechanism under the WTO working? Georgetown Law & Philosophy: John Mikhail (Law, Georgetown) Apologies, Excuses, and Some Whining The Calendar will go up late tonight. I've just finished doing four papers, two conferences, a lecture, and two workshops in four cities in an eight day period. My apologies, especially to anyone whose event was today. Smith and Prakash on "How to Remove a Federal Judge" Steve Smith and Sai Prakash (University of San Diego) have posted How to Remove a Federal Judge on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sunday, April 09, 2006
Legal Theory Calendar
University of Texas Law: Stefanie Lindquist (Vanderbilt), "Judicial Review by the Burger and Rehnquist Courts: Explaining Justices' Responses to Constitutional Challenges" UCLA Law: Professor Jerry Kang and Professor Gary Blasi, UCLA School of Law, "Behavioral Realism in Law: Implicit Cognition & Social Justice" NYU Law: Lily Batchelder Cardozo Intellectual Property Law Program: Srividhya Ragavan, University of Oklahoma, Replacing Sticks with Carrots: Is the Enforcement Mechanism under the WTO working? Georgetown Law & Philosophy: John Mikhail (Law, Georgetown)
University of Pennsylvania Tax Policy: Mitchell Kane University of Oxford-University of Texas Law Faculty Interchange
Ms. Mindy Chen-Wishart, Fellow in Law - Merton College, Oxford; University Lecturer and Director of Undergraduate Studies, Law Faculty - University of Oxford, "Undue Influence: Vindicating Relationships of Influence", Discussant: Professor Mark Gergen, UT School of Law Dr. Wanjiru Njoya, Fellow in Law - St. John's College, Oxford, "Employee Participation in Corporate Governance: the End, the Beginning of the End, or Perhaps the End of the Beginning?", Discussant: Professor Jens Dammann, UT School of Law Ms. Sandra Meredith, IT Training & Development Officer - Bodleian Law Library; Law Faculty - Oxford University, "The Oxford Law Legal Research Skills Programme", Discussant: Ms. Jeanne Price, Tarlton Law Library Dr. Katja Ziegler, Lecturer in Law, Fellow and Deputy Director of the Institute of European and Comparative Law - University of Oxford, "The Constitutionalisation of the British Constitution?: Recent Aspects of Constitutional Change in the UK Through 'the Two Europes' - Towards a Judicial Review of Statutes?", Discussant: Professor Ernie Young, UT School of Law Mr. Nicholas Bamforth, Fellow in Law - The Queen's College, Oxford; University Lecturer in Law - University of Oxford, "The Constitutional Status and Impact of the [UK] Human Rights Act 1998", Discussant: Professor H.W. Perry Jr., UT School of Law; Government Department Georgetown Law: Julie Cohen Georgetown Constitutional Law & Theory: Ted Ruger (law, Pennsylvania), The Chief Justice's Special Authority and the Norms of Judicial Power
University of Georgia Law: Alan Watson (UGA), Lord Mansfield: Judicial Integrity or its Lack: Somerset's Case NYU Legal History: Alison LaCroix, Golieb Fellow, NYU School of Law, "Drawing the Line: The Pre-Revolutionary Origins of Federal Ideas of Sovereignty."
Yale Law, Economics & Organizations: Professor Alison Morantz, Stanford, Law, Post-Accident Drug Testing & Workers' Compensation Claims in a Fortune 500 Company University of Illinois Criminal Law Colloquium, Susan Klein, University of Texas, Enhancing the Judicial Role in Criminal Plea and Sentence Bargaining University of North Dakota Indian Law: Erma J. Vizenor, "Tribal Sovereignty, the Federal Trust Responsibility, and Constitutional Reform" University of Michigan Law & Economics: Daniel Gervais, Ottawa, Intellectual Property and Development: Towards a Strategy UCLA Tax Policy & Public Finance: Dennis Ventry, Visiting Scholar in Taxation, UCLA School of Law, Suspicious Minds: The Uneasy Relationship Between Tax Lawyers and the IRS UCLA Law: Fernando Rámon Vegas Torrealba, Venezuelan Supreme Court Justice, "Democracy in Venezuela under the 1999 Bolivarian Constitution" Northwestern Tax: Lee Ann Fennell, Associate Professor, University of Illinois College of Law, "Taxation Over Time" NYU Tax: Mitchell Kane, University of Virginia Law School, "Risk and Redistribution in Open and Closed Economies." George Mason Law: Iliana Ilieva, GMU School of Law Levy Fellow Florida State Law: Barbara Fried, Stanford Law School, Contractarianism as the Site of Justice
University of Georgia Interntional Law: Roger Alford (Pepperdine), Foreign Relations as a Matter of Interpretation: The Use and Abuse of Charming Betsy UCLA Law: Scott L. Cummings, Acting Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law, "Transnational Public Interest Law" Legal Theory Lexicon: Hohfeld
Law students encounter the idea of right (moral or legal) early and often. But “rights talk” is frequently “loose talk.” Hohfeld is famous for exposing the ambiguity in the concept of a right and resolving that ambiguity with a typology of rights that distinguishes between claims, liberties, authorities, and immunities. This post is a quick and dirty introduction to Hohfeld for law students (especially first year law students) with an interest in legal theory. Types of Rights and Correlative Duties Lawyers tend to mush all legal rights together into a single category. The right to privacy, the right to freedom of speech, property rights, and civil rights—these diverse legal phenomena are frequently treated as if the “right” involved in these diverse cases was a single unambiguous type. Hohfeld’s first contribution was to distinguish different types of rights. Claim rights, for example, create corresponding obligations. Thus, my right to exclusive use of my land entails a corresponding duty of noninterference. You have a duty not to enter upon my land. But my property right also entails my liberty to use my land in a wide variety of ways—to build a house, plant a garden, and so forth. Correlated to that liberty is a correlative absence of inconsistent claim rights. You have no right to prevent me from building a house or planting a garden. Some legal rights involve powers over others. Thus, an employer has a right to control and direct the employee’s actions at work, and parents have authority over their children. Finally, there are immunities from authority. Thus, when children reach the age of majority or are legally emancipated they acquire immunities that disable the authority rights of their parents. Implicit in our discussion so far is Hohfeld’s second big idea, which is that each kind of right (claim, liberty, authority, and immunity) has a correlative legal consequence for others. Claim rights have correlative duties. Liberty rights correlate with an absence of claims. Authority rights correlate with liabilities. Immunities correlate with the absence of authority. Four Types of Rights The following list enumerates Hohfeld’s basic schema, identifying each kind of right and the correlative legal consequence. P is the party with the right. Q represents the person or group of persons on whom the right has a legal effect. X represents the object of the right.
Conclusion That’s Hohfeld in a very short nutshell! Many readers of Legal Theory Blog are about to take exams. If you are among them, good luck! Saturday, April 08, 2006
The Legal Theory Bookworm recommends Welfare and the Constitution (Princeton University Press page here) by Sotirios A. Barber. Here's a blurb:
Download of the Week The Download of the Week is Rational War and Constitutional Design by Jide Nzelibe and John C. Yoo. Here is the abstract:
Friday, April 07, 2006
Friday Calendar
Duke Law School: Animal Law Conference:
Notre Dame Law: Jacqueline Lipton, Associate Director, Frederick K. Cox International Law Center, Case Western Reserve University School of Law Location: Quinnipiac-Yale Dispute Resolution Workshop: Catherine A. Rogers, Louisiana State University, "Regulating International Arbitrators: A Consent-Based Approach to Enforcement of Misconduct-Tainted Awards" UCLA Media, Entertainment, and Culture Workshop:
University of Georgia Law: John Langbein (Yale), Trust Law as Regulatory Law University of Georgia International Law Colloquium: Diane Orentlicher (American University): "Whose Justice? Reconciling Universal Jurisdiction with Democratic Principles" University of Texas Law: Anthony Sebok, Brooklyn Law School, "Punitive Damages: From Myth to Theory" Villanova Law: Benjamin Barton, University of Tennessee College of Law William Mitchell Law: Michael Hurley, Counterterrorism Office, U. S. State Department> UCLA School of Law, Analytic Legal Philosophy Conference Schedule:
Two by Teubner Gunther Teubner (Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universität) has posted two papers on SSRN:
O'Connell on the Myth of War on Terror Mary Ellen O'Connell (Notre Dame Law School) has posted When is a War Not a War? The Myth of the Global War on Terror (ILSA Journal of International & Comparative Law, Vol. 12, No. 2, 2005) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Mikos on Eggshell Victims Robert A. Mikos (UC Davis – School of Law) has posted “Eggshell” Victims, Private Precautions, and the Societal Benefits of Shifting Crime (Michigan Law Review, Vol. 105, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Christensen on Case Analysis Leah M. Christensen (University of St. Thomas - School of Law) has posted Unmasking the Cognitive Mysteries of Case Analysis (Florida Coastal Law Journal, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Conference Announcement: Velleman at ANU
Hollis on Executive Federalism Duncan B. Hollis has posted Executive Federalism: Forging New Federalist Constraints on the Treaty Power (forthcoming, Southern California Law Review, Vol. 79) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Call for Papers: Works in Progress IP Colloquium
Conference Announcement: Lavender Law 2006
Thursday, April 06, 2006
Thanks and More Thanks Today, I'm in South Bend to deliver the annual "Natural Law Lecture" at Notre Dame. Thank you to Gerard Bradley and John Finnis for this especially welcome invitation. My lecture is entitled "Natural Justice" and it explores the connections between Philippa Foot and Michael Thompson's work on "Natural Goodness", on one hand, and virtue jurisprudence and natural law theory, on the other. And I also wanted to express my thanks to Andy Altman, Bill Edmundson, and Eric Seagall at Georgia State for their kind hospitality on Tuesday. I had an opportunity to present "The Supreme Court in Bondage" to the law faculty and "Virtue Jurisprudence: An Aretaic Theory of Law" to philosophy. And more thanks for all the wonderful comments. Conference Announcement: Institutionalizing the War on Terror at American University
A Taxonomy of Legal Blogs Ian Best has posted a comprehensive "taxonomy" of legal blogs--the best subject-matter guide (or "hierarchically organized outline") of which I am aware. Check it out! Thursday Calendar
UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Julie Tannenbaum, Assistant Professor of Philosophy University of California, Santa Cruz, THE "SHOULD" OF FULL PRACTICAL REASON Michigan State University: John C.P. Goldberg (Vanderbilt University) "The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs." Brooklyn Law School: Michael Perry, Emory University School of Law, The Constitutionality of Capital Punishment: Originalism, Yes; Scalia, No Boston University Law: Wendy Mariner Florida State Law: Darryl Brown, Washington & Lee, Rethinking Overcriminalization Fordham Law: Devon Carbado, Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law, "Racial Naturalization" George Mason Law: Christine Kymn, GMU School of Law Levy Fellow; Title: Strategic Signaling in Supreme Court Nominations (with Ross Davies) NYU Colloquim on Tax Policy & Public Finance: Ed McCaffery, USC Law School, “Shakedown at Gucci Gulch: A Tale of Death, Money, and Taxes” UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: Liam Murphy, Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy, New York University School of Law University of Michigan Law & Economics: Scott Baker, North Carolina, Incomplete Contracts in a Complete Contracts World University of Texas Law: Mike Tigar (American University), "Universal Rights & Wrongs: Roper vs. Simmons" Yale Legal Theory Workshop: Elizabeth Harman, New York University (Philosophy), The Mistake in "I'll Be Glad I Did It" Reasoning: Why Curing Deafness isn't Wrong, and Aborting You or Me Wouldn't Have Been Either Blumenthal on Emoitional Paternalism Jeremy A. Blumenthal (Syracuse) has posted Emotional Paternalism on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Helfer on Reservations & Treaty Design Laurence R. Helfer (Vanderbilt University - School of Law) has posted Not Fully Committed? Reservations, Risk and Treaty Design (Yale Journal of International Law, Vol. 31, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Nzelibe and Yoo on Rational War Jide Nzelibe and John C. Yoo (Northwestern University - School of Law and University of California at Berkeley School of Law) have posted Rational War and Constitutional Design (Yale Law Journal, Vol. 115, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sperino on McDonnell-Douglas Sandra Sperino (University of Illinois College of Law) has posted Flying without a Statutory Basis: Why McDonnell-Douglas is not Justified by any Statutory Construction Methodology on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Hamdani on the Cost of Ignorance Assaf Hamdani (Bar-Ilan University, Faculty of Law) has posted Mens Rea and the Cost of Ignorance on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Conference Announcement: Wittgenstein & Reason at Reading
Wednesday, April 05, 2006
Thursday Calendar
Notre Dame Law, Natural Law Lecture: Lawrence Solum, Natural Justice UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Julie Tannenbaum, Assistant Professor of Philosophy University of California, Santa Cruz, THE "SHOULD" OF FULL PRACTICAL REASON Brooklyn Law School: Michael Perry, Emory University School of Law, The Constitutionality of Capital Punishment: Originalism, Yes; Scalia, No Boston University Law: Wendy Mariner Florida State Law: Darryl Brown, Washington & Lee, Rethinking Overcriminalization Fordham Law: Devon Carbado, Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law, "Racial Naturalization" George Mason Law: Christine Kymn, GMU School of Law Levy Fellow; Title: Strategic Signaling in Supreme Court Nominations (with Ross Davies) NYU Colloquim on Tax Policy & Public Finance: Ed McCaffery, USC Law School, “Shakedown at Gucci Gulch: A Tale of Death, Money, and Taxes” UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: Liam Murphy, Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy, New York University School of Law University of Michigan Law & Economics: Scott Baker, North Carolina, Incomplete Contracts in a Complete Contracts World University of Texas Law: Mike Tigar (American University), "Universal Rights & Wrongs: Roper vs. Simmons" Yale Legal Theory Workshop: Elizabeth Harman, New York University (Philosophy), The Mistake in "I'll Be Glad I Did It" Reasoning: Why Curing Deafness isn't Wrong, and Aborting You or Me Wouldn't Have Been Either DeGirolami on Recoiling from Religion Marc O. DeGirolami has posted Recoiling From Religion on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Robinson on Desert Paul H. Robinson (University of Pennsylvania Law School) has posted The Role of Moral Philosophers in the Competition Between Deonotological and Empirical Desert on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Zamir on Contractual Equivalence Eyal Zamir (New York University - School of Law) has posted The Missing Interest: Restoration of the Contractual Equivalence (Virginia Law Review, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
O'Connell on the Security Council Mary Ellen O'Connell (Notre Dame Law School) has posted The Counter-Reformation of the Security Council (Journal of International Law and Relations, Vol. 1, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Garrett on Aggregation in Criminal Law Brandon L. Garrett (University of Virginia - School of Law) has posted Aggregation in Criminal Law (California Law Review, Vol. 95, 2007, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Tuesday, April 04, 2006
Not Legal Theory Department: The Long View of the US News Rankings Check out Dan Solove's nifty chart of the US News Rankings, US News Rankings: A Chart of the Past Decade, over at Concurring Opinions. Tuesday Calendar
Georgia State Philosophy: Lawrence Solum, Virtue Jurisprudence: An Aretaic Theory of Law UCLA Legal History: « Back Legal History Workshop: Clifford Ando, USC Law School, "Citizen and Alien in Roman Law" Northwestern Constitutional Theory: Einer Elhauge, Carroll and Milton Petrie Professor of Law, Harvard University, "Statutory Default Rules," Chapters 11, 12, and 14 Marquette Law: Jason Czarnezki, Marquette University Law School and Sara Benesh, University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, Ideology or Interpretative Philosophy: Testing the Legal and Attitudinal Models of the Seventh Circuit Topic: Ideology or Interpretative Philosophy: Testing the Legal and Attitudinal Models of the Seventh Circuit Georgetown Law: Ethan Yale Georgetown Colloquium on Constitutional Law & Theory: Oren Gross (law, Minnesota) Lund on Constitution Day Nelson Lund (George Mason University School of Law) has posted Is Constitution Day Constitutional? (Green Bag, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Macklem on Social Rights in Canada Patrick Macklem (University of Toronto - Faculty of Law) has posted Social Rights in Canada on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sales on Secrecy & National Security Investigations Nathan A. Sales (Georgetown University Law Center) has posted Secrecy and National-Security Investigations on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Hoffman on Vicarious Jurisdiction Lonny Sheinkopf Hoffman (University of Texas at Austin) has posted The Case Against Vicarious Jurisdiction (University of Pennsylvania Law School. Vol. 152, No. 3, pp. 1023-1103, 2004) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Workshop Announcement: Justice in Health Care at Lancaster
Book Announcement: The Founding Fathers and the Place of Religion in America by Labert
Book Announcement: After Brown by Clotfelter
Monday, April 03, 2006
Weekend Update On Saturday, the Download of the Week was and Contract Law Theory by Brian Bix and the Legal Theory Bookworm recommended Sorcerers' Apprentices by Artemus Ward and David L. Weiden. On Sunday, the Legal Theory Lexicon entry was "Holism" and the Legal Theory Calendar previewed the week's talks and conferences. Monday Calendar
Ruth Wedgwood of Johns Hopkins University, International Law & Organization Program, "UN Reform and Competitive Multilateralism"
NYU Law: Oren Bar-Gill University of Alabama Law: Mary Ann Case, University of Chicago Yale Workplace Law & Theory: NICOLE RAEBURN, Sociology, University of San Francisco, Inside Out: The Struggle for Lesbian, Gay, and Bisexual Rights in the Workplace Conference Announcement: Law, Religion, and Social Change at ANU
Sebok on Punitive Damages Anthony J. Sebok (Brooklyn Law School) has posted Punitive Damages: From Myth to Theory (Brooklyn Law School, Legal Studies Paper No. 57) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Chon on IP & Development Margaret Chon (Seattle University - School of Law) has posted Intellectual Property and the Development Divide (Cardozo Law Review, Vol. 27, pp. 101-190, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Lower on Natural Law & Agency Theory Michael L. Lower (University of Manchester) has posted Natural Law and Agency Theory on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Hoffman on Removal & the All Writs Act Lonny Sheinkopf Hoffman (University of Texas at Austin) has posted Removal Jurisdiction and the All Writs Act (University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 148, p. 401, 1999) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
Sunday, April 02, 2006
Legal Theory Calendar
Ruth Wedgwood of Johns Hopkins University, International Law & Organization Program, "UN Reform and Competitive Multilateralism"
NYU Law: Oren Bar-Gill University of Alabama Law: Mary Ann Case, University of Chicago Yale Workplace Law & Theory: NICOLE RAEBURN, Sociology, University of San Francisco, Inside Out: The Struggle for Lesbian, Gay, and Bisexual Rights in the Workplace
Georgia State Philosophy: Lawrence Solum, Virtue Jurisprudence: An Aretaic Theory of Law UCLA Legal History: « Back Legal History Workshop: Clifford Ando, USC Law School, "Citizen and Alien in Roman Law" Northwestern Constitutional Theory: Einer Elhauge, Carroll and Milton Petrie Professor of Law, Harvard University, "Statutory Default Rules," Chapters 11, 12, and 14 Marquette Law: Jason Czarnezki, Marquette University Law School and Sara Benesh, University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, Ideology or Interpretative Philosophy: Testing the Legal and Attitudinal Models of the Seventh Circuit Topic: Ideology or Interpretative Philosophy: Testing the Legal and Attitudinal Models of the Seventh Circuit Georgetown Law: Ethan Yale Georgetown Colloquium on Constitutional Law & Theory: Oren Gross (law, Minnesota)
NYU Legal History: Chaim Saiman, Golieb Fellow, NYU School of Law, “Legal Realism as American Exceptionalism”. Here's a snippet from this fascinating paper:
Villanova Law: Lisa Lehman, Catholic University, Columbus School of Law
Notre Dame Law, Natural Law Lecture: Lawrence Solum, Natural Justice UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Julie Tannenbaum, Assistant Professor of Philosophy University of California, Santa Cruz, THE "SHOULD" OF FULL PRACTICAL REASON Brooklyn Law School: Michael Perry, Emory University School of Law, The Constitutionality of Capital Punishment: Originalism, Yes; Scalia, No Boston University Law: Wendy Mariner Florida State Law: Darryl Brown, Washington & Lee, Rethinking Overcriminalization Fordham Law: Devon Carbado, Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law, "Racial Naturalization" George Mason Law: Christine Kymn, GMU School of Law Levy Fellow; Title: Strategic Signaling in Supreme Court Nominations (with Ross Davies) NYU Colloquim on Tax Policy & Public Finance: Ed McCaffery, USC Law School, “Shakedown at Gucci Gulch: A Tale of Death, Money, and Taxes” UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: Liam Murphy, Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy, New York University School of Law University of Michigan Law & Economics: Scott Baker, North Carolina, Incomplete Contracts in a Complete Contracts World University of Texas Law: Mike Tigar (American University), "Universal Rights & Wrongs: Roper vs. Simmons" Yale Legal Theory Workshop: Elizabeth Harman, New York University (Philosophy), The Mistake in "I'll Be Glad I Did It" Reasoning: Why Curing Deafness isn't Wrong, and Aborting You or Me Wouldn't Have Been Either
Duke Law School: Animal Law Conference:
Notre Dame Law: Jacqueline Lipton, Associate Director, Frederick K. Cox International Law Center, Case Western Reserve University School of Law Location: Quinnipiac-Yale Dispute Resolution Workshop: Catherine A. Rogers, Louisiana State University, "Regulating International Arbitrators: A Consent-Based Approach to Enforcement of Misconduct-Tainted Awards" UCLA Media, Entertainment, and Culture Workshop:
University of Georgia Law: John Langbein (Yale), Trust Law as Regulatory Law University of Georgia International Law Colloquium: Diane Orentlicher (American University): "Whose Justice? Reconciling Universal Jurisdiction with Democratic Principles" University of Texas Law: Anthony Sebok, Brooklyn Law School, "Punitive Damages: From Myth to Theory" Villanova Law: Benjamin Barton, University of Tennessee College of Law William Mitchell Law: Michael Hurley, Counterterrorism Office, U. S. State Department> UCLA School of Law, Analytic Legal Philosophy Conference Schedule:
Legal Theory Lexicon: Holism
As always, the Legal Theory Lexicon is aimed at law students (especially first year law students) with an interest in legal theory. And before we get on with it, a brief digression on the origins of the phrase. The idea of the law as a seamless web seems to be derived from a related idea--that thistory is a seamless web--found in the writiings of Frederic Maitland: "Such is the unity of all history that any one who endeavours to tell a piece of it must feel that his first sentence tears a seamless web." Frederic William Maitland, A Prologue to a History of English Law, 14 L.QUARTERLY REV. 13 (1898). The Law is a Seamless Web The idea that the law is a seamless web is familiar to almost every law student, but what on earth does this phrase mean? I think the best initial approach to this idea is to place it in the context of a common-law system. Suppose we have an unsettled question of law (e.g. a question about proximate causation in tort law). The question is unsettled in our jurisdiction, so there is no binding precedent—no prior decision of a higher court addresses the issue. But the lack of binding precedent does not imply that precedent is irrelevant to our question. The judge deciding our case with a tricky proximate cause question will want to look at the cases that deal with analogous issue. Her search for relevant case law might begin with cases on causation in tort law, but from there, it could lead to other issues and distinct doctrinal fields. For example, causation in tort is analogous to causation in criminal law. So our judge might base her reasoning in part on the way an analogous question was decided in the criminal context. And causation also arises in a variety of other legal contexts, leading our judge to move from fields that are closely related to torts, to more distant topics, including environmental law, administrative law, or even tax. Moreover, questions of proximate causation are only partly about causation, they also involve judgments about responsibility and reasonableness of conduct. In a common law system, the law is a seamless web in the sense that common-law ideas connect with one another in complex relationships of consistency and mutual support. A tremor in one region of the web of the law can in principle resonate in other region. Coherence and Holism The idea that holism involves wide and deep relationships of consistency and mutual support can be captured by introducing a related notion coherence. We might say that legal holists believe that a principle of coherence applies to the law as a whole. Each proposition of law ought to be consistent with every other proposition. Coherence can require more than mere consistency, however. A system of law achieves coherence at a deeper level if the normative justifications for legal propositions are consistent and mutually supporting. Cohererence can be local or global. The theory that the law is a seamless web can be rephrased as “the law is globally coherent,” and we might call that view “global legal holism.” Herculean Holism Ronald Dworkin’s theory, “law as integrity,” takes the idea that the law is seamless web to its logical conclusion. Dworkin illustrated his theory with an imaginary judge, Hercules. Because Hercules acts on the basis of the premise that the law is a seamless web, Hercules is required to construct the theory that best fits and justifies the law as a whole in order to decide any particular case. Given the holistic assumption that a change anywhere in the law can produce consequences everywhere, Hercules must constantly revise his theory—checking to assure himself that a recent change in the law of trusts does not have consequences for the best interpretation of the reasonable person standard in torts. Of course, actual judges are not like Hercules in this regard. No actual judge could possible construct a theory of the whole law of her jurisdiction. Actual judges must make do with theories that are local rather than global in nature. This is not to say that no actual judge has a tacit (or even partially explicit) view about the way the law hangs together as whole. Indeed, some real world judges have views that account for many different regions of the law. The most intellectual judges (Richard Posner, for example) have comprehensive legal theories that provide consistent explanations across many different doctrinal fields. But even these Herculean judges cannot actually produce a theory that fits and justifies all of the law—that would take longer than a human lifespan permits and most of the work would be terribly dull. Holism versus Particularism So far, I’ve been presenting a fairly sympathetic view of legal holism. But holism is a controversial view in the law. One might believe that holism is domain specific. That is, it might be the case that all of tort law hangs together, but that tort law is a more or less closed system. It could be the case that criminal law operates on a different set of principles than those that operate in tort, and hence that conclusions reached in criminal law are different from those reached in tort law on analogous questions. Of course, the domain of coherence could be a higher or lower level of generality than doctrinal field. Perhaps, perhaps all of private law is coherent, but public law operates on different principles. Alternatively, perhaps the common law and statutory law form two different fields—each coherent within its own realm but not consistent with each other. Moving to the other end of the spectrum, it might be that the law governing the tort of negligence is coherent, but that negligence and battery operate on entirely different principles. At the opposite end of the spectrum from global legal holism (“The law is a seamless web.”) there is at least logical space for a local legal particularism (“Take each case on its own merits.”). Is Holism Normative, Descriptive, or Interpretive? Before we come to a close, let’s address one final question: what kind of theory is legal holism? You may have notice that I’ve been deliberately ambiguous in my phrasing of holist claims using locutions like “is or ought to be.” One view of global legal holism is that it is a normative claim: the law ought to form a seamless web. Why? Well, that’s a big question, but one cluster of reasons for preferring consistency in the law centers around the rule of law values of predictability, certainty, and publicity. Another view of global legal holism is that it is a descriptive theory. As a matter of fact, judges (in common law systems) strive for consistency. The phrase—the law is a seamless web—is couched as a descriptive claim. Of course, this will be a special sort of descriptive claim, because no one thinks that the law actually is fully consistent at the global level. Yet another view of global legal holism is that it an interpretive theory. On this view, legal holism bears a relationship to the idea of the hermeneutic circle. The meaning of any given legal rule must be interpreted in light of the whole set of rules, and the meaning of the whole set depends on the meaning of the particular members. On this view, holism is quasi-descriptive and quasi-normative: legal interpretation both is imperfectly holistic and legal interpretation aims at global consistency. Conclusion The distinction between holism and particularism is quite useful. Once you begin to look, you will quickly find that many legal arguments depend on implicit assumptions about the presence or desirability of coherence in the law. In particular, it often edifying to look for how some legal arguments turn on assumptions about whether coherence should be global or local. Saturday, April 01, 2006
Legal Theory Bookworm The Legal Theory Bookworm recommends Sorcerers' Apprentices by Artemus Ward and David L. Weiden. Here's the blurb:
Download of the Week The Download of the Week is Contract Law Theory by Brian Bix. Here's the abstract:
|