Legal Theory Blog |
|
All the theory that fits! Home This is Lawrence Solum's legal theory weblog. Legal Theory Blog comments and reports on recent scholarship in jurisprudence, law and philosophy, law and economic theory, and theoretical work in substantive areas, such as constitutional law, cyberlaw, procedure, criminal law, intellectual property, torts, contracts, etc. RSS Links for Legal Theory Blog --Lawrence B. Solum (My Homepage at the University of Illinois) --My College of Law Directory Page --My Philosophy Department Directory Page --Email me --Legal Theory Annex (All the theory that does not fit.) --Legal Theory Lexicon (Basic concepts in legal theory for first year law students.) --My Publications on SSRN Noteworthy Posts Hiring Trends at 18 "Top" American Law Schools 2005-06 Report on Law School Entry Level Hiring 2004-05 Report on Law School Entry Level Hiring 2003-04 Report on Entry Level Hiring Legal Theory Bookclub: Lessig's Free Culture Getting to Formalism Water Wells and MP3 Files: The Economics of Intellectual Property Do Humans Have Character Traits? Naturalistic Ethics The Case for Strong Stare Decisis, or Why Should Neoformalists Care About Precedent? Part I: The Three Step Argument Part II: Stare Decisis and the Ratchet Part III: Precedent and Principle Fear and Loathing in New Haven A Neoformalist Manifesto Understanding the Confirmation Wars: The Role of Political Ideology and Judicial Philosophy Breaking the Deadlock: Reflections on the Confirmation Wars Going Nuclear: The Constitutionality of Recess Appointments to Article III Courts Archives 09/01/2002 - 09/30/2002 01/01/2003 - 01/31/2003 02/01/2003 - 02/28/2003 03/01/2003 - 03/31/2003 04/01/2003 - 04/30/2003 05/01/2003 - 05/31/2003 06/01/2003 - 06/30/2003 07/01/2003 - 07/31/2003 08/01/2003 - 08/31/2003 09/01/2003 - 09/30/2003 10/01/2003 - 10/31/2003 11/01/2003 - 11/30/2003 12/01/2003 - 12/31/2003 01/01/2004 - 01/31/2004 02/01/2004 - 02/29/2004 03/01/2004 - 03/31/2004 04/01/2004 - 04/30/2004 05/01/2004 - 05/31/2004 06/01/2004 - 06/30/2004 07/01/2004 - 07/31/2004 08/01/2004 - 08/31/2004 09/01/2004 - 09/30/2004 10/01/2004 - 10/31/2004 11/01/2004 - 11/30/2004 12/01/2004 - 12/31/2004 01/01/2005 - 01/31/2005 02/01/2005 - 02/28/2005 03/01/2005 - 03/31/2005 04/01/2005 - 04/30/2005 05/01/2005 - 05/31/2005 06/01/2005 - 06/30/2005 07/01/2005 - 07/31/2005 08/01/2005 - 08/31/2005 09/01/2005 - 09/30/2005 10/01/2005 - 10/31/2005 11/01/2005 - 11/30/2005 12/01/2005 - 12/31/2005 01/01/2006 - 01/31/2006 02/01/2006 - 02/28/2006 03/01/2006 - 03/31/2006 04/01/2006 - 04/30/2006 05/01/2006 - 05/31/2006 06/01/2006 - 06/30/2006 07/01/2006 - 07/31/2006 Blogosphere New: --PrawfsBlog (Group BLog) --Balkinization (Jack Balkin) --Crescat Sententia (Group Blog) --Crooked Timber (Group Blog) --De Novo (Group Blog) --Desert Landscapes (Group Blog) --Discourse.Net (Michael Froomkin) --Displacement of Concepts (Group Blog) --Election Law (Rick Hasen) --Freedom to Tinker (Ed Felten) --The Garden of Forking Paths --How Appealing (Howard Bashman) --Instapundit (Glenn Reynolds) --Is That Legal? (Eric Muller) --Law & Society Weblog (Group Blog) --The Leiter Reports (Brian Leiter) --Lessig Blog (Lawrence Lessig) --Marstonalia (Brett Marston) --Paper Chase @ Jurist (Bernard Hibbitts) --Political Arguments (Group Blog) --ProfessorBainbridge.com (Stephen Bainbridge) --Pea Soup (Group Blog) --Punishment Theory (Group Blog) --The Right Coast (Group Blog) --SCOTUS Blog (Group Blog) --Sentencing Law and Policy (Douglas Berman --Statutory Construction Zone (Gary O'Connor) --TaxProf Blog (Paul Caron) --Volokh Conspiracy (Group Blog) Websites of Interest +Arts and Letters Daily +Conference Alerts +Daily Whirl +fa.philos-l +Economic Theory News +Encyclopedia of Law and Economics +Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program (U.C. Berkeley) eScholarship Repository +Law and Politics Book Reviews +Metapsychology Book Reviews +Notre Dame Philosophical Review +Online Papers in Philosophy +PoliticalTheory.info +SSRN Most Recent Uploads More Blogs of Interest --Althouse (Ann Althouse) --Asymmetrical Information (Jane Galt) --bIPlog (Group Blog) --The Blawg Review (Group Blog) --Brad DeLong --The Buck Stops Here (Stuart Buck) --Copyfight (Group Blog) --A Copyfighter's Musings (Derek Slater) --The Curmudgeonly Clerk --Daniel Drezner --Discriminations (John and Jessie Rosenberg) --Eastmania (Wayne Eastman) --EveTushnet.com (Eve Tushnet) --Freespace (Timothy Sandefur) --Furdlog Frank Field --Ideoblog (Larry Ribstein) --The Importance Of (Ernest Miller) --The Indiana Law Blog (Marcia J. Oddi) --Infothought (Seth Finkelstein) --IPKat (Jeremy Phillips and Ilanah Simon) --Law and Economics Blog (Greg Goelzhauser) --Law Dork (Chris Geidner) --Law Meme (Group Blog) --Lee Blog Edward Lee --Legal Ramblings (Steven Wu) --Lenz Blog (Karl-Friedrich Lenz) --Letters of Marque (Heidi Bond) --The Light of Reason (Arthur Silber) --Matthew Yglesias --philosophy.com (Gary Sauer-Thompson ) --Public Defender Dude --Rodger A. Payne's Blog --Southern Appeal (Group Blog) --Strange Doctrines/A> --Susan Crawford blog --A Taxing Blog (Group Blog) --That's News to Me (Group Blog) --Thoughts Arguments and Rants (Brian Weatherson) --Three Years of Hell to Become the Devil --The Trademark Blog (Martin Schwimmer) --Troppo Armadillo (Ken Parish) --Technology 360 --Tutissima Cassis (Nate Oman) --Unlearned Hand --Weatherall's Law (Kim Weatherall) --WENDY.SELTZER.ORG (Wendy Seltzer) --yin (Tung Yin) Legal Theory Programs & Websites --Arizona State Committee on Law and Philosophy --Cambridge Forum for Legal and Political Philosophy --Columbia Law School Center for Law and Philosophy --Columbia Legal Theory Workhsop --Georgetown University Law Center--Colloquium on Constitutional Law and Theory --Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program (U.C. Berkeley) --Kadish Center for Morality, Law, and Public Affairs (U.C. Berkeley) --NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political and Social Philosophy --Oxford Jurisprudence Discussion Group --Oxford Legal Philosophy --Oxford Centre for Ethics & Philosophy of Law --Queen's University Belfast Forlum for Law and Philosophy --Rutgers Institute for Law and Philosophy --UCLA Legal Theory Workshop --University of Pennsylvania Institute for Law and Philosophy --University College London: Colloquium in Legal and Social Philosophy --University of Chicago Law And Philosophy Workshops --University of Chicago: John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics Workshop --University of San Diego Institute for Law and Philosophy --University of Texas Law and Philosophy Program --Yale Law School: Legal Theory Workshop Links to Law School Workshops +Australian National University Faculty Events +Boston University +Buffalo +Columbia Center for Law and Economic Studies +Florida State +Fordham +George Mason +George Washington--IP Workshop Series +Georgetown Colloquium on Intellectual Property & Technology Law +Georgetown Law Workshops +Georgetown Law and Economics Workshop +Georgetown Law & Economics Workshop Series +Hofstra +University of Illinois +Lewis & Clark +Loyola Marymount +New York University +NYU Legal History Colloquium +Northwestern Law Colloquium +Oxford Law Events +Rutgers, Camden +Stanford Center for Internet & Society +Stanford Law School Olin Series +UCLA Colloquium +UCLA Legal History Workshop +UCLA Tax Policy --University of Chicago: John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics Workshop +University of Michigan Law and Economics +University of San Diego Colloquium Series +University of Texas Colloquium Series +Vanderbilt Scholarly Programs & Events Calendar +Villanova +Washington & Lee Faculty Workshops +Yale Law, Economics & Organizations Workshop Calendars & Events +Aristotelian Society +British Society for Ethical Theory +Conference Alerts +Events in Analytic Philosophy in Europe (and Overseas Countries) +The Philosophical Calendar +Philosophy Now Calendar +Political Science Online Upcoming Conferences +SSRN Professional Announcements Other Programs --Australian National University, Research School of Social Science, Philosophy Seminars --Boston University Philosophy Colloquia --Brown University Philosoophy Upcoming Events George Mason Workshop in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics --Harvard University, Philosophy Colloquia --MIT Philosophy Colloquia --New York University, Philosophy Events --Oxford: Events at the Faculty of Philosophy --Princeton University: Philosophy Department Talks --Princeton University: Political Philosophy Colloquium --Princeton University: Public Law Colloquium --Princeton University: Seminar in Law and Public Affairs --Tulane Philosophy and Center for Ethics & Public Affairs Seminars --University College, London: Political Theory Seminars --University of Arizona Philosophy Colloquia --University of Bristol Philosophy Research Seminars --University of California at Berkeley Philosophy Events --University of California at San Diego Philosophy Colloquia --University of Chicago Political Theory Workshop --University of London, School of Advanced Study, Philosophy Programme --University of Manchester Politics & Philosophy Research Seminars --University of Melbourne Philosophy Events --University of North Carolina: Philosophy Speakers --University of Pennsylvania: Philosophy Colloquiua --University of Pittsburgh Philosophy Calendar --Yale Philosophy Department Talks Some Legal Theorist Homepages --Robert Alexy (Christian Albrechts University Kiel) --Randy Barnett (BU) --Brian Bix (Minnesota) --Jules Coleman(Yale Law & Philosophy) --Ronald Dworkin(NYU & University College) --John Finnis(Oxford and Notre Dame) --John Gardner (Oxford) --Brian Leiter (Texas) --Micahel Moore (Illinois) --Dennis Patterson (Rutgers, Camden) --Stephen Perry (NYU) --Richard Posner (University of Chicago & USCA7) --Joseph Raz (Oxford and Columbia) --Jeremy Waldron (Columbia More to come! Journals Specializing in Legal Philosophy --American Journal of Jurisprudence --The Journal of Philosophy, Science, and Law --Law and Philosophy --Law and Social Inquiry --Legal Theory --Oxford Journal of Legal Studies Legal Theory Resources on the Web Entries from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy +Austin, John +justice, distributive +justice, as a virtue +legal philosophy, economic analysis of law +legal reasoning, interpretation and coherence +legal rights +liberalism +libertarianism +naturalism in legal philosophy +nature of law +nature of law, legal positivism +nature of law, pure theory of law +republicanism From the Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence +Natural Law Theory: The Modern Tradition From the Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies +Law as an Autonomous Discipline From the Examined Life A Critical Introduction to Liberalism Papers & Articles +Virtue Jurisprudence Organizations +American Political Science Association(APSA) +American Society for Political and Legal Philosophy (ASPLP) +Association of American Law Schools(AALS) +Internationale Vereinigung fur Rechts und Sozialphilosophie(IVR) +Law and Society Association +Midwest Political Science Association (MPSA) My Postal Address Lawrence B. Solum University of Illinois College of Law 504 East Pennsylvania Ave Champaign, IL 61820 USA |
Monday, March 31, 2003
McCain-Feingold Decision Hold Up The decision on the constitutionality of the BCRA is very late. Why? Rick Hasen reports on a story filed by Nina Totenberg, filled with scandal and intrigue. Read Rick's two posts in the following order: Bertram on the Difference Principle Chris Bertram of the valuable Junius writes:
G.A. Cohen's Critique of the Difference Principle I must admit to being almost utterly mystified by the traction that Gerry Cohen's critique of the difference principle has developed. Simplifying Cohen's argument for the purpose of bloggin, the core idea is that incentives should not be necessary for citizens who have internalized the difference principle. They ought simply to be motivated by the difference principle to work so as to make the least-advantages as well off as they can be. (Among the simplifications is that I am using the phrase "well off" and not discussing Rawls's idea of the "primary goods.") But this argument both misunderstands the point of justice as fairness and would lead to absurd consequences. Cohen Misses the Fundamental Idea of Reciprocity Cohen's argument misses a fundamental premise of the Rawls's theory. The point of justice as fairness is not to benefit one group--the least advantaged. Rather, justice as fairness requires reciprocity--all must benefit. Cohen's argument would lead to a basic structure that (with respect to the primary goods) is aimed at the benefit of the least-advantaged, with no reciprocal advantage for other groups. This same point can be made another way. If Cohen were right, everyone who was not in the least advantaged group would be obligated to adopt the welfare (loosely speaking) of the least advantaged as their own goal in life. So long as there was a least advantaged group, no one outside that group would be entitled to their own comprehensive conception of the good. No one could pursue art, music, religion, or building a better Internet as a life plan, unless their action would produce the greatest benefit for the least well off as compared to any alternative course of action. From a Rawlsian perspective, Cohen's critique self destructs. Workshops Today Here is today's roundup:
At NYU's Faculty Workshop series, Fred Schauer (Visiting at NYU & Harvard, Kennedy School) is on the calendar. Sunday, March 30, 2003
Milestones Department This evening the number of visits for Legal Theory Blog went over 10,000 for the month of March. Although a smallish number by the standards of Instapundit or the Volokh Conspiracy, it seems quite respectable for a weblog that focuses on scholarship and ideas related to legal theory. Is Yoda a Legal Theorist? Check out Political Theory Blog for startling evidence that the answer to this question is yes. And while you are at it, take a look at Micah's post on judicial junkets. Wittgensteinian Politics I am usually somewhat skeptical about appropriations of Wittgenstein--especially in the post-modern vein. Along those lines and courtesy of the really super PoliticalTheory.info, here is a paper by Melinda Kovács (Rutgers, Political Science) entitled Play nice: Towards a Wittgensteinian politics. Kovács essay detours hither and yon, ending:
Zittrain on Internet Points of Control Jonathan Zittrain's paper entitled Internet Points of Control somehow slipped past me a week or two ago. I heard Jonathan do an earlier version of this at Boston College in the Fall--must reading for cyberprofs and others interested in legal regulation of the Internet. Here is a taste:
Saturday, March 29, 2003
Back from Brazil I've returned from the ICANN meeting in Brazil. Here is a guide to my posts on the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers:
Blogging from Brazil 2--should new top level domains be taxonomized? Blogging from Brazil 3--ICANN is the only place with more arguments about procedure than a law school faculty meeting! Blogging from Brazil 4--Coase on the FCC and the ICANN Policy Dialog. Blogging from Brazil 5--Stuart Lynn proposed a "beauty contest" for new top level domains. Blogging from Brazil 6--Is ICANN on a slippery slope to recapitulating the FCC? Blogging from Brazil 7--The tone of debate shifts toward market-oriented approaches & the future of ICANN. A Law Student Blog with a Difference Whatever your position on the war, you will be interested in Intel Dump. The blog of UCLA law student and former Army Officer. Read his informative post on Urban Warfare. More Hasen on Judicial Nominations While I was Flying Up From Rio, Rick Hasen has been more good stuff on judicial nominations. Here is his post on filibustering in the context of the war. And here is a post on the nomination and possible filibuster of Priscilla Owen. Rick may need to change the name of his Blog from Election Law to Judicial Nominations. New on SSRN Some new papers went up late yesterday. Here are the highlights:
Friday, March 28, 2003
Downward Spirals Department My colleague Rick Hasen (who thinks that we are on a roller coaster & not a downward spiral) posts re the possibility that Judge Priscilla Owen, nominated for a vacancy on the United States Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, may be filibustered. New Papers on SSRN Here are the new papers on SSRN:
My colleague Jan Costello (Loyola Marymount) offers Why Have Hearings for Kids If You're Not Going To Listen?: A Therapeutic Jurisprudence Approach to Mental Disability Proceedings for Minors, forthcoming in the University of Cincinnati Law Review. Barbara Fried (Stanford) has given us Ex Ante/Ex Post forthcoming in The Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues. Habermas at the Royal Institute of Philosophy Jurgen Habermas--surely one of the greatest philosophers of the era--speaks today at the Royal Institute of Philosophy. His lecture is entitled: On Tolerance, Democracy and Cultural Rights. The venue is Beveridge Hall, Senate House, Malet Street, WC1, London. I tried to book my trip to the ICANN meetings in Brazil through London, but I just couldn't make it work! Thursday, March 27, 2003
Balkin on Scalia on Originalism Jack Balkin's blog Balkinization is one of the best--although I frequently find myself disagreeing with Jack's articulate and trenchant posts. He has a doosy on originalism up today. Here is a snippit:
--Originalism May Be Internally Constrained for Principled Reasons. Originalism is only a module within some larger theory of the constitution and interpretation. Other modules in the theory may trump originalism in particular situations. Actually, I think that it is at this level that consistency is quite difficult to achieve. For example, some rule-of-law originalists believe stare decisis trumps originalism, and that originalist results should only be achieved via incremental common law changes. (We move from an unoriginaist interpretation to an originalist one by making marginal adjustments where there are gaps, contractictions, or ambiguities in the precedents.) --Originalist Solutions May Be Unavailable Because of Case Dynamics. Because our system is adversaril, parties shape records, lower court decisions, and the argument set before the court. This shaping process may render the originalist solution outside the choice set before the Court. Lawrence v. Texas Erik Jaffe (of the Ancient and Respected Order of Volokh Bloggers) attended the oral argument in Lawrence v. Texas (the challenge to the Texas sodomy laws) yesterday. Here is his very nice post. And there is also a post from the ever-helpful SCOTUSBLOG. And here is the L.A. Times story. Blogging from Brazil 7 Today was the last day of the Rio De Janeiro meeting of the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN). Here are a few last thoughts and impressions about the meeting:
Topsy Turvey Economics On the bus from the public forum to dinner on Wednesday night, I had one of those big fat a ha moments. Here is what it was about. Stuart Lynn (who steps down as President of ICANN today) described his sTLD beauty-contest plan as an RFP process. When thinking about the root, here is how Lynn sees things. He sees TLD name service as something that ICANN is responsible for providing. Therefore, he thinks of the TLD operators (e.g. Verisign, the ccTLD operators, etc.) as vendors--from whom ICANN buys a product (name service at the TLD level). In other words, ICANN is the customer! But wait a second! That is exactly backwards. ICANN holds a valuable resource--the root. ICANN sells root service to TLD operators, who then sell TLD name service (via the registrars as intermediaries) to you and me. ICANN is in the business of allocating a resource, and not buying a service. No wonder ICANN is having trouble developing a rational resource allocation policy! How can you develop a system for rationing the scarce root resource, if you don't even know you have a scarce resource to allocate! A Change in Tone The worst thing to do with a resource is waste it. That has been ICANN's basic policy toward the root--waste the resource by maintaining a virtually static root. In November 2000, ICANN held a beauty contest that expanded the root just a little bit. In Rio, ICANN set in motion yet another beauty contest that would expand the root an even smaller bit. But there was also a change in tone. Vint Cert articulated an important principle regarding the root. He suggested that the fundamental principle that should govern expansion of the root is that new TLDs should be allowed in the root as long as they will do no harm. Let me repeat that. Cerf's Principle: A new TLD should be allowed in the root so long as it does no harm. But wait, there's more. When the meeting started, the notion of a market-driven allocation process looked like it was in big trouble. But by the end of the public forum, the factions within ICANN that are holding on to the idea of a static root were on the defensive. (Their slogan is: Don't push the problems of the second level to the top. I would put it: Don't allow the economic miracle of millions of SLDs pollute the last part of the DNS to be managed by top-down engineering, the pure and holy root.) Even those who advocate wasting the root were beginning to talk about the inevitabiity of market approaches. Even Stuart Lynn was talking about demand-driven approaches! Of course this is ICANN, never underestimate the possibilities for strategic blocking in a consensus-driven, bottom-up, entrenched-stakeholder organization. But the consensus at the dinner after the public forum was that the tone of the debate had changed. The defenders of a static root are only going through the motions. Beauty contests are under attack. Market-driven approaches are on the intellectual offensive. The Road Ahead What challenges will ICANN face in Montreal, Carthage, and beyond? Here are some of the issues that are likely to emerge:
--Root Expansion. Sooner or later ICANN must face the BIG policy question of root expansion. This would be a suitable topic for a task force that includes members from outside ICANN's internal structure, e.g. an economist. (On his way out of the airport, Vint Cerf collared me and told me that he needed to have a conversation about economists with me. OK, Vint! --The Digital Divide. I am convinced that ICANN should stay out of the general Digital Divide issue, but ICANN is inevitably involved in the particular DD issues that are inevitably raised by the ICANN's resource allocation responsibilities for the name and number space. All of the gTLDs are first world focused. IDN (Internationalized Domain Names) creates the possibility of new gTLDs using IDN. One of ICANN's highest priorities should be IDN gTLDs for LDCs. How's that for acromania! In plain English, ICANN should faciliate the creation of new .coms, .orgs, etc. that use characters sets other than the very restricted set--Roman alphabet, Arabic numeral plus hypen and underscore--that is currently permitted. This is especially true for LDCs (Less Developed Countries). If someone doesn't jumpstart IDN gTLDs for LDCs, they will be a long time coming. The IDN standard has been formulated, so ICANN needs to move on this issue. Thursday is Workshop Day Here is the roundup:
At George Mason, Michele Boardman (George Mason and the Volokh Order of Noble and Prolific Bloggers) presents Self-Regulation of Critical Infrastructure through Insurance: Can the Turtle Play Sentry to the Hare?. At the University of Michigan's Olin Series, Scott Masten (Michigan) presents Contracting in the Absence of Specific Investments and Moral Hazard: Understanding Carrier-Driver Relations in US Trucking. At Yale's Legal Theory Workshop series, Arthur Applepaum (Harvard, Public Policy) presents Legitimacy in a Bastard Kingdom. As I began to read his paper, I had one of those great big head-spinning a-ha! moments. After you read the next sentence, you may say to yourself, "I didn't know Solum was so dense," but here goes. Applebaum's paper opened my eyes to the obvious point that normative political legitimacy is closely related to the legitimacy of heirs--hence his title. I have been been puzzeled by the concept of normative legitimacy for years. Here is a taste of the fine work in Applebaum's paper:
The other distinction is between the word legitimacy, the concept or idea of legitimacy, and particular conceptions of legitimacy, the content of the concept. “Fine word, legitimacy!” Edmund says with irony. It is a fine word, but we need to trace its changing senses over time to distinguish the word from the idea or ideas it expresses. The same word, of course, can come to refer to different concepts—a “civil right” is not a polite uppercut to the jaw—and different words—“authority” is the closest cousin here—can refer to the same concept. I have, a moment ago, offered a rough account of the concept by saying that legitimacy is the moral right to rule, but if we understand conceptual analysis as the exercise of marking off apt boundaries for fruitful argument so that we neither talk past each other nor beg the question, we may discover that this rough draft needs some editing. Finally, the concept or idea of legitimacy can be filled out in different ways. We can both agree that we are talking about the same idea, legitimacy, but disagree about its content: criteria for how you get legitimacy and what it gets you. At the University of San Diego's Law, Economics, and Politics Workshop series, Joy Freeman (UCLA & Bren School of Management, UC Santa Barbara) and J.R. DeShazo (UCLA, Public Policy) present The Congressional Competition to Control Delegated Power. Here is a taste from the abstract:
Wednesday, March 26, 2003
Blogging From Brazil 6 ICANN is a truly interesting organization. Here we are in Brazil making decisions regarding the future of the global internet, and just anyone (me, in this case) can just walk in off the street and make a speech to the Board of Directors at the Public Forum. The topic was the expansion of the root space. In particular, lame-duck ICANN President Stuart Lynn make a very thoughtful presentation of his proposal for a limited round that would allow only sponsored Top Level Domains into the root. Lynn's proposal is for a complex, criteria driven, beauty-contest model. Only nonprofit, global, membership organizations would be eligible. Some of the criteria for evaluation were vague: does the proposal add value? Others are intrustive: does the sponsoring organization have adequate procedures for internal communciation and input--surely none of ICANN's business. The Better Should Not Defeat The Good Earlier in the meeting, the Chair of the Board, internet pioneer Vint Cert, made a plea for incremental improvement. Don't let incremental improvements be defeated on the ground that something even better is on the horizon. Yes, of course. In many contexts, incrementalism is just common sense. But in other cases an incremental improvement may lead to unintended consequences. Unintended Consequences of an sTLD Beauty Contest So what might the unintented consequences of an sTLD beauty contest be? Here are some possibilities?:: Cost-Based Rationing to the Non-Profit Sector--Lynn was aiming at objectivity. To that end, he proposes multiple teams of evaluators who will rate applications on the basis of an elaborate point-system. Moreover, some of the criteria encourage expensive applications. For example, community support is a criterion, but demonstrating deep and wide community support can be very expensive. The sTLD space is intended for nonprofit organizations, and it therefore seems quite odd to allocate the root space allocated for non-profits by imposing substantial application expenses. Wouldn't it make sense, instead, to create a very lean, low-cost mechanism for entry into the sTLD space? How about automatic entry into the root for international non-profit membership organizations that can demonstrate that they have or have contracted for the necessary back end technical competence? :: A Slippery Slope--But a more serious unintended consequence of sTLD beauty contests is the danger that by creating an elaborate beauty contest mechanism, ICANN is taking a second step towards institutionalization of the beauty-contest model. Think about the following scenario:
+Step Two: The Summer 2003 Montreal round--a formalized sTLD beauty contest with mutliple-criteria, a point system, and multiple independent evaluation teams. +Step Three: A 2004 round--the formalized beauty contest mechanism is extended from sTLDs (nonprofit, membership organizations) to other categories of gTLDs (perhaps nonmembership nonprofits or even commercial gTLDs). Junius on Recent Political Philosophy Texts Chris Bertram has a really nice round-up of recent political philosophy texts. One of the texts is by the late Jean Hampton, who in her first year at UCLA was my first teacher in legal and political philosophy. I still mourn her tragic death at a very early age. I was therefore touched and pleased by Chris's praise of the book. Check out Chris's fine post. Post Scirpt Chris adds a bit more here. New on SSRN Three very interesting new papers have recently been posted on SSRN:
Robert Rabin (Stanford) posts The Quest for Fairness in Compensating Victims of September 11, forthcoming in the Cleveland State Law Review. Thomas Grey (Stanford) offers Judicial Review and Legal Pragmatism. Here is a taste from the abstract:
Comments on the ICANN sTLD Beauty Contest Proposal Have Been Posted Karl Manheim and I have posted a comprehensive set of comments on the new ICANN proposal to establish beauty-contest process for the evaluation of new sponsored Top Level Domains. Here are the relevant links:
--Criteria to Be Used in the Selection of New Sponsored TLDs. (The proposal posted on the ICANN website.) --gTLD-auctions.net (a collection of news and links on the issue.) --New: Comments on the sTLD beauty contest proposal have been posted on ICANN Watch. The link to specific post is here. Blogging from Brazil 5 Those who have been following my Blogging from Brazil posts know that one of the issues that I have been following is root expansion. Top level domains (TLDs), such as .com, .org, and so forth are controlled by ICANN. In November of 2002, ICANN decided to add several new TLDs, including three sponsored by non-profits (.aero, .coop, and .museum). My colleague Karl Manheim and I have posted a policy paper to SSRN entitled The Case for gTLD Auctions: A Framework for Evaluating Domain Name Policy and we have established a website that collects news and resources at gTLD-auctions.net. ICANN's complex internal machinery has been munching on this issue for some time, and a variety of ideas are floating around the ICANN idea space. New ICANN "Beauty Contest" Proposal Posted Yesterday Yesterday, the ICANN staff posted a new document on ICANN's website. The document is entitled Criteria to Be Used in the Selection of New Sponsored TLDs (click on the link). The core idea of the proposal is to create a limited number of new sponsored Top Level Domains (sTLDs). Only non-profit well-resourced membership organizations would be eligible to established sTLDs. The proposal suggests a number of highly subjective criteria by which proposals would be evaluated, and a complex out-sourced beauty-contest process for numerical ranking of the proposals. The new ICANN document suggests that this proposal could serve as a template for future root expansion! The Worst of All Possible Worlds The sTLD beauty contest proposal makes sense as a short-run solution to a short-run problem. The November 2000 round was, in many respects a process disaster. On the plus side, the root name space was expanded. But on the minus side, ICANN's Board was forced to engage in an ad hoc beauty constest procedure, with no objective criteria on which to base its decision. Quite naturally, disappointed applicants were unsatisfied with the process. ICANN put itself in the position of being open to charges of arbitrary, unfair, and illegitimate action. Why not let in three more gTLDs sponsored by non-profit, membership organizations on the model of .aero, .coop, and .museum? The problem is that ICANN could not just let three more in. Some open process needed to be established. The sTLD beauty contest proposal is intended to provide a more rational beauty contest, and to get the ICANN Board out of the role of judging. Bravo! But in the long run, this is absolutely the worst decision ICANN could possibly make. The problem is beauty contests never work. We have known this since Ronald Coase's devastating critique of the FCC beauty contest approach. No matter how hard the FCC tried, beauty contests were arbitray and unfair. The Fundamental Problem The fundamental problem with the beauty contest approach is that it is just plain impossible for a board to do even a decent job of determining which innovative uses of a resource will succeed and which will fail. Experience teaches this lesson to those who judge resource-allocation beauty contests. So the judges do what they can do. The judges can't evaluate the worth of the proposals, so they focus on the characteristics of the contestants! And this is exactly what the new ICANN sTLD beauty contest proposal does. There are elaborate criteria regarding the qualifications of the applicants and vague, mushy criteria for the criteria regarding the merits of the actual new sTLD. Down the Slippery Slope If the ICANN board approves the sTLD beauty contest proposal, the results are predictable. A formalized, rationalized, bureaucratized beauty-contest mechanism will have been established. In the beginning, it will be applied to one round of sTLDs and it will be an improvement over the ad hoc November 2000 round. The ICANN Board will then be on the slippery slope to a beauty-contest model. At the bottom of the slippery slope is the worst mechanism devised by humankind for the allocation of a scarce resource! More later! Downward Spirals Department Rick Hasen has another articulate and intelligent post. He argues that we are not in the midst of a downward spiral, but rather are on a "roller coaster" of politicization. More on this later. Tuesday, March 25, 2003
Political Theory Blog I've added a link to Micah Schwartzman's Political Theory Blog to the sidebar. Once again, thanks to Chris Bertram at the wonderful Junius for prompting me to do this. Blogging from Brazil 4 Lee McKnight (Syracuse) organized a small group on Monday night to discuss ideas for expanding the gTLD name space. Before I report on the conversations, some background.
Back to Monday Night So what happened Monday night? Of course, ICANN meetings involve stakeholders and wanna-be stakeholders. Nokia was at the meeting to explain their .mobile TLD concept--essentially a plan for a new top level domain that would be used by the telcos and mobile phone manufacturers to create domain names for mobile phones. McKnight presented the Mueller/McKnight auction plan. Then the questions started flying, and they were really, truly amazing--in a good and bad way. Here is a sample of the ideas that were bandied about:
Short Run Focus The participants in the ICANN process, quite naturally, have a very short-run focus. They are (and should be) interested in making money. So the parties that are the most interested in expansion of the root (i.e., in having new TLDs) are those who have applied to ICANN in the past and not yet been granted their string--.mobile and .web were represented Monday night. So the stakeholders and wanna-be stakeholders want ICANN to approve their new gTLDs right now or as soon as possible. They are in favor of gTLD auctions, if it will speed up their getting their gTLD and opposed to auctions if auctions will slow down their getting their gTLD. Of course, many existing stakeholders have an interest in preventing expansion of the root. Verisign (the operator of the .com registry), in particular, may have an interest in blocking new unrestricted gTLDs that would compete with .com. The interaction between these groups makes it very difficult to get bottom-up consensus on an auction proposal. What is Value Another question that is frequently raised about gTLD auctgions is: "Will the gTLDs that win the auctions have value?" Or will such gTLDs "add value?" Huh? Of course, it is possible that firms will bid for value-less gTLDs, but the whole point of a market is to insure that resources are put to their most valuable use. The gTLDs that are established as a result of an auction are exactly the gTLDs that the market tells us are most likely to add value. The "value added" question seems, at bottom, to be based on the assumption that someone (the questioner, ICANN's board) can do a better job of estimating value than the market. Sometimes this is the ending point of the conversation, but some interlocutors seem to have another idea in mind. They seem to believe in some concept of intrinsic value, i.e. value that cannot be measured by prices. Well maybe. But here is the problem. No one agrees on what constitutes intrinsic value. I suspect that in the context of new gTLDs, the idea of intrinsic value sometimes boils down to "value from the point of view of a network engineer." If so, then: (1) the market can account for this kind of value, because it affects costs and benefits, and (2) the Internet is for end users, not for network engineers. New on SSRN Several interesting papers have gone up on SSRN recently:
Richard Pildes (NYU) uploads The Inherent Authoritarianism in Democratic Regimes. Here is a taste from the abstract:
Victor Romero (Pennsylvania State) has made available Decoupling 'Terrorist' from 'Immigrant': An Enhanced Role for the Federal Courts Post 9/11 and Critical Race Theory in Three Acts: Racial Profiling, Affirmative Action, and the Diversity Visa Lottery, forthcoming in the Albany Law Review Emily Buss Doss (Chicago) uploads two pieces: The Speech Enhancing Effect of Internet Regulation & Children's Associational Rights? Why Less Is More. Adam Pritchard (Michigan) has shared Should Congress Repeal Securities Class Action Reform?. Monday, March 24, 2003
The Semantic Web Courtesy of EDdventure, this regarding Tim Berners-Lee at the PC Forum yesterday:
Klimchuk on the Autonomy of Corrective Justice Dennis Klimchuk (Western Ontario) has a nice piece coming out in the Oxford Journal of Legal Studies for March. Here is the abstract:
New Paper on TLD Expansion One of the most important Internet governance questions concerns the management of the Top Level Domain (TLD) space. Top Level Domains like .com, .edu, and .org are a scarce resource in the economic sense, and the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN) is charged with the task of resource allocation. So far, ICANN policy has resulted in severe shortages in the TLD space. Firms want to create new TLDs, but ICANN has been slow to respond to the demand. Given Ronald Coase's devastating critique of the Federal Communicatons Commission's "beauty contest" model of resource allocation, one might think that the one approach to TLD expansion that ICANN would have managed to avoid would be ad hoc hearings, in which ICANN Board Members attempt to pick the best TLD's based on their own estimation of the proposals value, but that is exactly what ICANN has done so far. Recently the Business Constituency (a subgroup within ICANN's byzantine structure) has suggested what it calls "differentiated expansion," essential a plan to "taxonomize" top level domains. New domains would be allowed only if they are limited in scope and sponsored by a nonprofit organization. No new unrestricted top level domains would be allowed. You can get the Business Constituencies Position Paper here.. My colleague, Karl Manheim, and I have written an extensive analysis and critique of the BC's position. You can download The Inefficiencies of Differentiated Expansion by clicking on the title. Post Script New: We have another, longer, paper that argues that case for an auction-based approach to gTLDs: The Case for gTLD Auctions: A Framework for Evaluating Domain Name Policy. Click on the title to go the SSRN download page. Blogging from Brazil 3 I've just ducked out of the traditional dog-and-pony show, with the ICANN Board answering questions from the Business, Intellectual Property, and ISP constituencies. Vint Cert drew a round of applause when he suggested that the time for discussion of structural reform was over and stated that he would focus on the substantive issues faced by ICANN. It is remarkable how ICANN manages to consume itself in endless debate about structure--to the almost total exclusion of the issues that face the name and number space. The result is that ICANN has been unable to make rapid progress on issues like Internationalized Domain Names, TLD expansion, and IPv6--which actually impact users of the Internet. ICANN meetings are almost the only place in the entire universe where there is more discussion of process than in a law school faculty meeting! MacIntyre on Harrison on Sidgwick Don't miss Alasdair MacIntyre's review of Ross Harrison's Henry Sidgwick. Get it here, courtesy of the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Monday Workshops Here is today's roundup:
At the University of Cardiff, Chris Bertram (of Junius fame) presents Global Justice and Democracy. Chris argues "that there's an asymmetry between what distributive justice requires in the intra- and international cases that flows from the different ways in which the capability for democratic citizenship is secured in each of these arenas." At Vanderbilit, David Rosenberg (Yale) presents Nuisance-Value class Action Settlement Problem: Mandatory Summary Judgment. At Georgetown Richard Primus (Michigan) workshops Equal Protection and Disparate Impact: Round Three. At Florida State Jonathan Cohen (University of Florida) does The Culture of Legal Denial. Sunday, March 23, 2003
Blogging from Brazil 2 It is about 2:00 a.m. in Rio de Janeiro. My colleague, Karl Manheim, and I spent the day at the meetings of the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers here in Rio--spending most of the day working on a response to the "differentiated expansion" proposal outlined in a position paper issued by Business Constituency of the Generic Names Supporting Organization. The core idea of the position paper is that top level domains should be "taxonomized," i.e. that each new .com or .edu should have linguistic meaning. The Business Constituency paper argues, in addition, that there no new "unrestricted" top level domains should be created. Karl and I argue that this approach is both inefficient and anticompetitive. We will post our paper at gTLD-auctions.net tomorrow. In the meantime, it is time for me to grab some sleep! Howell and Lewis on Presidential Agencies William Howell (Stanford, Political Science) and David Lewis (Princeton, Woodrow Wilson) have recently uploaded Agencies by Presidential Design, forthcoming in the Journal of Politics. Here is a taste form their abstract:
Balkin versus Buck--Update & Update to Update Jack Balkin & Stuart Buck have a very interesting debate going on Scalia's theories of constitutional interpretation and their application to affirmative action. Here are the posts:
Buck's demurrer. Balkin's plea in abatement. Buck's Sur-Reply. Balkin's Latest Rejoinder. Here is an excerpt from Balkin's latest:
Sigler on Govier Check out Mary Sigler's fine review of Trudy Govier's Forgiveness and Revenge, get it here. Courtesy of the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Smith on Metaethics in Adjudication Dale Smith's article The Use of Meta-Ethics in Adjudication is just out in the Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. Here is an abstract:
Saturday, March 22, 2003
gTLD-Auctions.net My colleague, Karl Manheim and I have put up a website that collects information and resources relating to domain name policy in general and the expansion of the root in particular (i.e. new top level domains, such as .com, .org, etc.). Karl and I have just completed a paper titled gTLD Auctions: A Framework for Evaluating Domain Name Policy. Along similar lines, Milton Mueller and Lee McKnight of Syracuse University have posted their White Paper, The post-.COM Internet: A Five-Step Process for Top Level Domain Additions. ICANN's management of the root is a fascinating topic--it brings together issues from public choice theory, law & economics, and institutional economics--all in the context of the management of the global Internet. I will be blogging from the ICANN meeting tomorrow (Sunday) and all of next week. In the meantime, you can get the papers & additional infomration at gTLD-Auctions.net. Catching Up Department Fred Dallmayr has a nice review of Jurgen Habermas Jürgen's Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity. Get it here. Downward Spirals Department Yesterday, Rick Hasen posted a thoughtful comment on the question whether the highly-partisan judicial selection process is in a downward spiral of politicization—responding to my earlier post—here.. Rick argues:
Monsters and Apparitions Rick also writes:
The Bottom Thinking about the bottom of the downward spiral has real utility. As I have argued previously, the downward spiral is the product of two factors: (1) asymmetrical perceptions—each side believes the other side is escalating, leading to further retaliatory escalation (going nuclear); (2) short-run thinking—each side is myopically focused on the next election and the next term of the Supreme Court and hence, both sides have lost sight of the long run—the enormous benefits produced by the rule of law. The point of my parade of horribles is not that we are at the bottom of the spiral today. Thank goodness, we are not even close. The point of thinking about the bottom is to remind ourselves that we do not want to go there. Both left and right share a long-run interest in maintaining the rule of law. Rick’s post suggests one way to de-escalate—tone down the rhetoric—on both sides. I’ve suggested another technology of de-escalation—look to the long run. There initial steps can lead to others. Republicans should withdraw the threat of “going nuclear.” Democrats should not blue slip and filibuster systematically. Both left and right can and should realize that de-escalation is in their own long-run self interest. My Agenda Rick understands that I have a "radical" agenda. My hope is that the current downward spiral can serve as a wake-up call, a crucial perception-altering event. Further descent on the downward spiral is not inevitable. A depoliticized, neoformalist judiciary supported by a cooperative judicial-selection process has, in the past, been a stable cooperative equilibrium. Neoformalism is the norm in most advanced judicial systems outside of the United States, but there is no reason to believe that party politics in the United States are so different from those elsewhere that we are doomed to judicial politicization. The rule of law is not pie in the sky; it is a realistic option, inside the feasible choice set. A downward spiral can become an upward spiral. Both parties can come to realize that it is in their long-run self-interest to appoint virtuous judges. The cardinal judicial virtue is the virtue of justice—the disposition to decide in accord with the law and not on the basis of politics. Hopes and Fears My hope is that we are close to a turning point—that when the talk turns to going nuclear, both sides may realize it is time to call off the war. My fear is that the long-run costs of politicization are not yet sufficiently vivid to transform the short-run orientation into a long-run orientation—that both sides must deploy their nuclear options before either side will “get it.” Moves Toward the Final Death Spiral What if my fears are warranted? How might escalation continue? Rick has explored several possibilities, including the use of recess appointments to the Supreme Court and suspension of the cloture rules for judicial confirmations. Democrats would surely attempt to retaliate, and if they lack the means to retaliate now, they will bide their time and act when they regain control of the Presidency or the Senate. On the bench, intensely partisan political judges may come to believe that the blatanly political decision making is simply an ordinary and acceptable tactic in the struggle for political power. I see no reason to believe that the downward spiral will terminate any point short of what Rick has called "mutually assured destruction." Conference on Kant's Philosophy of Value At the University of Hertfordshire Centre for Normativity and Narrative, there is a conference on Kant's Philosophy of Value today. Here are the speakers & topics:
Blogging from Brazil 1 For the next several days, I will be blogging from the meeting of the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN) in Brazil. These meetings are fascinating, and there are enormously important issues in the air. Here is a preview of some of the topics that I will be covering:
Expansion of the Root--Dotcom, .org, .edu, etc. are top level domains. The supply of such TLDs has been artificial constrained. My colleague Karl Manheim and I have just completed a paper comparing ICANN's management of the domain name system with FCC regulation of the broadcast spectrum and the telephone numbering system. Our paper argues that new top level domains should be added to the root by an auction mechansim. More on this soon. Internet Governance--ICANN is a strange beast. It is much like a regulatory agency, but it is a private-nonprofit corporation organized under California law. ICANN's governance procedures are byzantine and highly controversial. The most controversial event recently was ICANN's decision to hold global elections for seats on the ICANN board, followed by the decision to replace elections with a very complicated system. Again, more on this from the road! Friday, March 21, 2003
Broken Windows The University of Chicago Chronical has a very nice short piece on Bernard Harcourt's Illusion of Order: The False Promise of Broken Windows Policing. Here is a taste:
Downward Spirals Department I'm on the Road to Rio with my colleague Karl Manheim, but I have just enough time during a layover in Miami to alert you to Rick Hasen's excellent post in our ongoing debate re the politicization of the judiciary. Surf here. Rick is relentless! I'll compose a reply in the air and post tomorrow. In the meantime, read Rick's eloquent, intelligent, and persuasive post. 24 Hour Hiatus There will be only infrequent posts to this blog for the next 24 hours, as I travel with my colleague Karl Manheim to the meetings of the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers in Brazil. Tomorrow, look for a post on the ICANN meeting, the topics that I will cover from Brazil, and the importance of Internet Governance to legal theory. On Sunday, look for a post on important recent scholarship on Internet governance issues. Downward Spirals Department Is the current battle over President Bush's nominations to various federal courts part of a downward spiral of escalating politicization of the judicial selection process? I've argued that it is, but my colleague Rick Hasen believes that Democratic tactics are simply tit for tat--responses to equivalent moves by Repubicans in the last round--when Clinton was President. In particular, Rick argues that Democratic use of blue slips is paralleled by Republican use during the Clinton years. See his post here. Let me concede that blueslipping, by itself, does not establish escalation, but add a comment. Both Democrats and Republicans percieve that their own moves are tit for tat, but that the moves of the other side are escalation. In other words, we face a problem of asymmetrical perceptions. This is one of the important preconditions for a downward spiral. If each side percieves that the other sides moves are escalatory, then each side sees escalation on their own part as the rational move. Hence, the Republican discussion of "going nuclear"--see Rick's original discusson and then scroll up in his blog for further posts. If I am right about the downward spiral, the consequences can be profound. The end-point of politicization is very grim indeed--with judges openly battling for poltical agendas, ordinary tort and contract cases turning into the opportunity for the distribution of pork, and the political branches retaliating against the judiciary when there are differences in party control. We don't want to go there. More from SSRN More new scholarship on SSRN:
Peter Schuck (Yale) uploads Groups in a Diverse, Dynamic, Competitive, and Liberal Society: Comments on Owen Fiss's 'Groups and the Equal Protection Clause' Lucio Baccaro (International Institute for Labour Studies) offers Civil Society Meets the State: A Model of Associational Democracy. Lucian Bebchuk (Harvard) gives us The Case for Empowering Shareholders. Francesco Parisi (George Mason), Norbert Schulz (Bayerische Julius Maximilians Universität Würzburg), and Ben Depoorter (Yale) offer Simultaneous and Sequential Anticommons. If you are not familiar with the now-burgeoning anti-commons literature, this paper is a nice way to catch up. Here is a teeny tiny little bite, that gives you the flavor of the issue:
Maskin on Political Accountability of Judges Courtesy of the invaluable Economic Theory News, Erik Maskin (Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton) has made available his paper The Politician and the Judge: Accountability in Government, from the UCLA (economics) Theory Workshop series. Here is a taste from the abstract:
Fiss Fest! The University of Miami is putting on a conference titled, Fiss's Way: The Scholarship of Owen Fiss, today and tomorrow (March 21-22, 2003). Here is the lineup for this very exciting event:
Workshop Today At Vanderbilt's Legal Theory Workshop series, Maxwell Stearns (George Mason) presents A Beautiful Mend: A Game Theoretical Analysis of the Dormant Commerce Clause Doctrine. Catchy title Max! Thursday, March 20, 2003
Jus in Bello From the Independent today:
:: Aquinas on War. :: Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations (paperback ed. 2000). :: There is an entry titled Just War Theory in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy :: Another collection of links. :: Vincent Ferraro, Principles of the Just War. :: Alexander Moeser's paper Just War Theory in a Changing World. :: Wendy McElroy, Libertarian Just War Theory. :: American Center for Law and Justice Just War Theory and Iraq. :: Interview with Robbie George (NRO). Off Topic Department Thanks to the ever-helpful Howard Bashman at How Appealing for a link to the BBC war reporter's blog. This should satisfy even Eugene's (of the Most Serene Volokh Blog Repubic) thirst for fresh news--see his post. Downward Spirals Department Rick Hasen has been blogging recently on the mysterious Washington Times story indicating that the Republicans may "go nuclear" in response to the Democratic filibuster of Miguel Estrada. Another reader sent me a link to an NRO Outline Story indicating further escalation from the Democrats:
Post Script Hasen has a new post on the history of the recess appointments clause in the context of judicial appointments. Post Post Script Rick replies to the above, arguing that the Michigan Democrats are engaged in simple tit for tat. Well, yes, it is tit for tat. But in a standard iterative prisoners dilemma, you don't expect tit for tat to continue, on and on, for many rounds (in the real world, years) of play. Is this an escalation? I don't know, but I think it is at least unusual to use the blue-slip procedure to block all Presidential nominees from an opposition party state. But as Rick notes in his response, Jesse Helms did this same thing during the Clinton Administration! Thanks Rick. At University College London Today Michael Freeman delivers the J. A. C. Thomas Lecture A Time to Live and a Time to Die. Barry on Inequality and Responsibility I just finished reading Brian Barry's workshop paper (Kadish, today). The central idea in the paper is what Barry call's the principle of responsibility:
Teaching the Ethics of War Courtesy of Arts & Letters Daily, there is a marvelous post on The Chronical of Higher Education Website from tomorrow's issue. Sharon E. French (U.S. Naval Academcy) posts When Teaching the Ethics of War Is Not Academic. Christopher Eberle (who also teaches at Annapolis) was recently at the University of San Diego Institute for Law and Philosophy for a debate with Michael Moore, David Brink, and Michael Perry. At dinner after the debate, Chris talked about the experience of teaching ethics to midshipmen--fascinating. Here is an excerpt from Shannon's essay:
New on SSRN Here is today's collection of links to new and interesting papers posted on SSRN:
Ulrich Haltern (Humboldt Universität zu Berlin ) uploads Pathos and Patina: The Failure and Promise of Constitutionalism in the European Imagination. Oliver Gerstenberg (Harvard) posts Expanding the Constitution Beyond the Court: The Case of Euro-Constitutionalism. More Hasen on Estrada Zip over to Rick Hasen's Election Law Blog for his latest on the possibility that the Republican's will go nuclear on Estrada. Balkin versus Buck Jack Balkin & Stuart Buck have a very interesting debate going on Scalia's theories of constitutional interpretation and their application to affirmative action. Here are the posts: Thursday is Workshop Day It is a bit difficult to focus on the day-to-day given the war, but here is today's roundup:
At George Mason, Jonathan Klick is workshopping Does Tort Reform Help States Retain Physicians and Does It Matter? Florida State has an excellent series. Today Fernando Teson does Kant, Intervention, and Trade: A Response to my European Critics. You go Fernando, especially those French critics! And at Boston University, Alan Macurdy presents Sovereignty in a Normative Universe: Felix Cohen and the Conflict of Laws. Alan, any chance you could put up a link? And at the Kadish Center for Morality, Law, and Public Affairs (U.C. Berkeley) Brian Barry (Columbia, Philosophy) offers Does Responsibility Undermine Equality? Wednesday, March 19, 2003
Closer to Being on Topic Rick Hasen has an excellent post on a mysterious Washington Times story, suggesting that the Republicans may go nuclear on the Estrada Nomination. Off Topic There is a very fine piece of journalism about Saddam Hussein in The Atlantic. Here is the link. This excerpt gives the flavor of the piece:
New on SSRN Here is the Wednesday roundup:
Sharona Hoffman (Case Western Reserve) offers Corrective Justice and Title I of the ADA. Here is a taste of Hoffman's paper:
Legal History Corner Thanks to Timothy Sandefur for calling my attention to this story in the Los Angeles Times, which as Tim writes, "is about the discovery of dozens of "freedom cases" filed by slaves in St. Louis before the Civil War. There were a number of theories they argued, but most important was the argument--which found support in Blackstone and in an early case called Somerset v. Stewart, and was thus often called the "Somerset" theory--that once a slave was brought into free territory, he was automatically freed. This argument was obviously the big loser in Dred Scott v. Sandford." Workshop Today At the University of San Diego, Eric Posner (Chicago) workshops Social Norms in Tort and Contract Law. Ongoing Debates Department Political scientist Brett Marston continues the ongoing debate about the role of politics in judicial selection. Here is his post. Watch this space for a reply to Marston's intelligent remarks. And don't forget to check our Rick Hasen's contributions to this controversy in his excellent Election Law Blog. Volokh on Iraq as a Precedent Eugene Volokh, author of The Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope (long version in HTML or PDF) has a piece in Slate on slippery slopes and the argument that the attack on Iraq would set a dangerous precedent. Here is a flavor of his argument:
Tuesday, March 18, 2003
Hathaway on Path Dependence Oona Hathaway's very, very smart Path Dependence in the Law: The Course and Pattern of Legal Change in a Common Law System just went up as an abstract on SSRN. Here is a tasty morsel from the abstract:
Gaus Reviews Eberle Courtesy of the marvelous PoliticalTheory.info, this link to Gerald Gaus's review of Christopher Eberle's Religious Convictions in Liberal Politics. Here is the way it starts:
Catching Up Department I somehow missed Jack Balkin's upload to SSRN of The Proliferation of Legal Truth. What a mistake! Here is a taste:
Schauer on Neutrality Fred Schauer--superscholar extraoridinaire--has posted a new paper to SSRN this morning. The title is Neutrality and Judicial Review. Here is the abstract:
Legality of the War Department Courtesy of Paper Chase, Australian law professors assert the legality of the imminent war. Here is a link. Here is the core of the argument:
Resources on Just War Theory Here is an updated set of links to resources on the Web:
:: Aquinas on War. :: Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations (paperback ed. 2000). :: There is an entry titled Just War Theory in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy :: Another collection of links. :: Vincent Ferraro, Principles of the Just War. :: Alexander Moeser's paper Just War Theory in a Changing World. :: Wendy McElroy, Libertarian Just War Theory. :: American Center for Law and Justice Just War Theory and Iraq. :: Interview with Robbie George (NRO). Monday, March 17, 2003
Sunstein on Moral Heuristics Cass Sunstein is working in the vineyard of heuristics again. This time, he has a very intriguing and original paper, Moral Heuristics, just up on SSRN today. He introduces the paper with the following claim:
More on SSRN Here are this afternoon's new papers:
Thomas Poole (Nottingham) gives us Dogmatic Liberalism? T.R.S. Allan and the Common Law Constitution, forthcoming in the Modern Law Review. Roger Brownsword (Sheffield) posts Stem Cells, Superman, and the Report of the Select Committee, forthcoming in the Modern Law Review. Mark Mildred (Nottingham) offers up Cost-sharing in Group Litigation: Preserving Access to Justice, forthcoming in the Modern Law Review. New Papers on the Net Here are new papers of interest to legal theorists, courtesy of SSRN and invaluable Economic Theory News:
Colin Camerer, George Loewenstein and Drazen Prelec post Neuroeconomics: How neuroscience can inform economics. Here is a taste:
Blanche Grosswald (Rutgers, Social Welfare) posts The Right to Physician–Assisted Suicide On Demand, forthcoming in Law & Policy. Monday Workshops Here is the Monday roundup of workshops from hither and yon:
At Loyola Marymount, Robert Pushaw (Pepperdine) workshops Why Are Liberals Embracing Shared Constitutional Interpretation? Here is a taste of Bob's intriguing and very provocative paper:
Sunday, March 16, 2003
Lessig on Spectrum Commons Larry Lessig has a nice column on spectrum commons in CIO Insight. Get it here. Reactions Department Oswego State University political scientist Brett Marston offers a very thoughtful reaction to the recent exchange between Rick Hasen and myself on judicial selection. Here is a taste:
By academic training as well as sentiment I find Rick Hasen's argument more persuasive, at least to the extent that he argues that the political nature of Supreme Court judging cannot be denied, and any change to the nominations process should take that into account. This is basically Chuck Schumer's position as well. Is it surprising that a Senate Democrat is pushing the "Court is political" argument? Not really. Not the Ideal Speech Situation Chris Bertram (author of the always delightful Junius) blogged today on the tragic assasination of Zoran Djindjic, the Prime Minister of Serbia, an extraordinary intellectual, and a former PhD student with Jurgen Habermas. Here is a profile courtesy of Fox. Grafitti near the murder site reads: "Who have you abandoned us to, Zoran?"--link. Wu on United States v. Morrison I just caught up with Yale Law student Steven Wu's Monday post on United States v. Morrison. Bravo! Saturday, March 15, 2003
Feasibility One of the most important, but least theorized, issues in debates over law and public policy concerns the question: what is the set of feasible choice? That is, which choices are realistic and which are utopian? How can we tackle this issue? Here are some ideas garned from recent writing by legal theorists:
--Slippery Slopes. Eugene Volokh's superb article, The Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope (long version in HTML or PDF) provides another angle of attack on the feasible choice set question. Volokh is interested in how a choice at one time (t1) can constrain the feasible choice set at another time (t2). Eugene's article is very helpful, because it contains a rich, analytically-sharp analysis of the various mechanisms by which choices are constrained. Although this analysis is set in the context of slippery slopes, it actually has much wider application and would provide a helpful starting point for a general theory of feasibility. (BTW, there is a short version of Eugene's article here, but read the long version.) --Possible Worlds Semantics. Yet another tool for analyzing feasiblity suggested by one of all-around super genius Gottfried Leibniz's best ideas--the notion of a possible world. Here is the one-minute philosopher's version:
--Feasibility and Framing. The way an issue is framed frequently is relevant to what constitutes the feasible choice set. The most compelling example of this phenomenon is time frame. Here is one version. Some choices are outside the feasibility set in the short run, but inside the set in the long run. For example, in my recent discussion of political ideology in judicial selection, I argued that neoformalism was outside the short-run set of feasible choices, but inside the set in the long rune. Friday, March 14, 2003
Ongoing Debates Department Rick Hasen has posted his reply to my most recent contribution to our ongoing debate about political ideology and judicial selection. You can find his post here. Rick's posts on this topic have been very thoughtful, and I have learned a great deal from them. Thank you Rick. More New Papers on SSRN Here is the roundup so far today:
James Anderson (Boston Colllege, Economics) and Oriana Bandiera (London School of Economics and Political Science, Economics) upload Traders, Cops and Robbers. Here is the abstract of this intriguing paper:
Thursday, March 13, 2003
New on SSRN There are some very interesting papers that have just gone up on SSRN. Here is the list:
Nickolai Levin (clerk to Judge Morris Arnold) has posted Constitutional Statutory Synthesis, forthcoming in the Alabama Law Review. Here is a taste:
Thursday is Workshop Day Here is today's roundup:
At Princeton's Political Philosophy Colloquium, Tracy Strong (UC-San Diego) The Tragic Ethos and the Spirit of Music. At Michigan's Olin Series, Alan Auerbach (Berkeley) Is There a Role for Discretionary Fiscal Policy?. Wednesday, March 12, 2003
Catching Up Department I missed a very interesting paper by CARLOS E. Gonzalez (Rutgers, Newark) titled Popular Sovereign Versus Government Institution Generated Constitutional Norms: When Does A Constitutional Amendment Not Amend the Constitution?. Here is a taste from his abstract:
New on SSRN Here is today's roundup:
Larry Backer (Penn State) uploads Retaining Judicial Authority: A Preliminary Inquiry on the Dominion of American Judges. Dworkin on Interpretation Ronald Dworkin (University College, London & NYU) has another book in the works, and he workshopped a chapter at the Colloquium in Legal and Social Philosophy at UCL. The paper is entitled Interpretation, Morality and Truth. I haven't yet read the whole paper, but Dwokin seems to be aiming at a synthesis on his work on objectivity in morality with his master theory of interpretation. Here is a small taste:
Tuesday, March 11, 2003
Today's Workshops This is the second day of the Oxford Legal Philosophy Colloquium 2003. Here are the offerings:
Stephen Perry (Pennsylvania) delivers Harm, counterfactuals, and Compensation with comments by Andrew Simester (Nottingham). Klaus Günther (Frankfurt) offers Responsibility and democracy with comments by Tony Honoré (Oxford). James Penner (London) gives Interpretive concepts and essentially contested concepts with comments by Nicos Stavropoulos (Oxford). Ongoing Debates Department: Political Ideology and Judicial Selection Over the past few weeks, Rick Hasen and I have engaged in an ongoing debate about the role of political ideology in judging. This is the fourth and final installment in my reply to Rick’s post from last Monday. Restoring the Rule of Law This all began with my argument that judges should be selected for their possession of the judicial virtues rather than their ideology. Rick Hasen argued that the courts are already ideological, and neoformalism, the normative theory which contends that judges should decide on the basis of law rather than politics, is unrealistic. Rick argues that the best we can hope for is minimalism, political judging that is constrained. Yesterday, I offered an informal game theoretic model of judicial selection. That model predicted that a strategy of tit for tat could produce a stable cooperative equilibrium, with both sides appointing formalist judges. Under certain conditions, however, a downward spiral of retaliation might develop, with opposing parties engaged in an escalating war of politicization. Two factors that might trigger the downward spiral are: (1) Asymmetrical Perceptions—each side might exaggerate its own cooperativeness while missing cooperative signals from the other side, and (2) Short Sightedness--for various reasons, one or both sides might overvalue the immediate benefits of politicization and undervalue the long run benefits of the rule of law. Once a downward spiral has set in, both sides might come to believe that a stable cooperative equilibrium is impossible. De-escalation How might a downward spiral be stopped? One end point for a downward spiral is the bottom—the point at which the judiciary has been thoroughly politicized and judging has become a blatant struggle for political control combined with the dispensation by the judiciary of political rewards and punishment. But if we are not yet at the bottom, could a downward spiral be halted or even transformed into an upward spiral of cooperation—ending in a stable cooperative equilibrium? Can we de-escalate? The Mechanisms of Cooperation To restore cooperation, the underlying causes of the downward spiral must be addressed. We must transform asymmetrical perceptions into accurate and shared belief. Short sightedness must be replaced with a view to the long range. If these transformations could be accomplished, the self-interest of both sides should lead to the adoption by both liberal and conservatives of a tit-for-tat strategy, which in the long run leads to the appointment of formalist judges as a stable cooperative equilibrium. End the Propaganda War Is it possible for both the left and the right to get an accurate view of the politicization of judging? Here are some suggestions:
One mechanism might be to have a trusted third-party evaluate judicial candidates on the basis of their possession of the judicial virtues, especially the virtue of justice—the disposition to decide on the basis of law rather than political ideology. But in order for this strategy to work, the intermediary must be trusted. This makes is extremely important that the intermediary itself act (and be perceived as acting) in an apolitical fashion. And in order to insure that intermediaries be perceived as apolitical, it is crucial than neither side should lobby the intermediary. Although the ABA may have been perceived at one time as a neutral intermediary, it is clear that this perception is no longer shared by both liberals and conservatives. The creation of a new third-party intermediary is one possible technology for minimizing the problem of asymmetrical perceptions. If a new intermediary is created, it is vitally important that both sides refrain from lobbying the intermediary, because such lobbying is likely to undermine trust—whether or not the lobbying has any real impact or not. Critical Self-Evaluation Yet another mechanism for minimizing asymmetrical perceptions is for each side to engage in critical self-evaluation. This means that both liberals and conservatives need to look critically at their own judicial selections, and attempt to realistically access the extent to which they have nominated judges or justices who adhere to the rule of law in an even-handed fashion. Such critical self-examination need not be aimed at the general public. What is required is that the players on both sides of the judicial selection game disabuse themselves of the notion that, “We select fair and even-handed judges, but they select biased judges.” Transparency in the Judicial Selection Process In addition, asymmetrical perceptions are likely to be reinforced by asymmetries in the availability of information. In practical terms, it is the President and the nominee who have the power to reduce these asymmetries. Of course, the more politicized the candidate, the more likely it becomes that openness in the confirmation process will lead to opposition. But candidates who are strongly committed to the rule of law should benefit from a transparent confirmation process. Transparency is likely to increase the opposition’s belief that the candidate truly is committed to the rule of law. Candidates should be forthcoming, both making themselves available to answer questions and answering appropriate questions with candor. The use of handlers should be minimized and their role constrained. Back Off Attack Mode Yet another way to end the propaganda war is to back off the use of unfair or distorted attacks on judicial nominees. This takes me back to the starting point of my debate with Rick Hasen. Adam Cohen’s New York Times Op Ed was an unfair attack on Justice Deborah Cook. I still don’t know whether I support or oppose Justice Cook, but I do know that distortions of her record will reinforce the downward spiral of politicization that we are currently experiencing. Minimalism as a Transition Strategy And this brings me back to Rick Hasen’s suggestion. Rick argued that my first-best solution, neoformalism, is unrealistic. Instead, he suggested an alternative strategy, which he called minimalism—a constrained form of political judging. Such constraint might well be an appropriate transition strategy. To the extent that both liberal and conservative judges are constrained, political actors become more likely to believe that cooperation in the judicial selection process can result in an equilibrium that benefits both sides. Moreover, I agree with Rick that a neoformalist big bang is not realistic. The downward spiral of politicization has progressed too far. Too many political judges have already been appointed. We cannot expect judges who lack the virtue of justice to forgo political calculation—that would go against the grain of their character. Restoring the rule of law is a long run project. Minimalism may very well be a strategy that could play a rule in halting, and even reversing the downward spiral. But if Minimalism Is Realistic in the Short Run, the Neoformalism Is Realistic in the Long Run Suppose Rick is right. Suppose that minimalism is a realistic strategy for breaking the downward spiral, and reestablishing a stable cooperative equilibrium. Once we begin to move up the spiral, then the situation begins to change. If judges are not initially selected for their possession of the virtue of justice, they are at least selected for moderation and willingness to compromise. But why would there be a ceiling on the upward spiral? As trust is restored and both sides begin to focus on their long run self-interest, each side becomes more confident that appointing and confirm judges who are strongly committed to the rule of law is, in the long run, a win-win strategy. As such judges are appointed, the behavior of the courts begins to change, which in turn would lead to even greater mutual trust. The question is not whether the Supreme Court could transform itself into a neoformalist tribunal next term. The question is whether actions we take now could set the stage for a transformation of the judiciary in the long run. Convergence So in the end, I think that my position and Rick’s position converge on several points. We agree that a continued downward spiral of politicization (Rick’s “mutually assured destruction”) should be avoided. We agree that in the short run, steps should be taken to reduce politicization, and that Rick’s preferred option, minimalism, is one such step. We agree that a neoformalist big bang is not a realistic option. But I am not sure whether we agree about the long run. Perhaps Rick thinks that minimalism is the best we can do. Perhaps Rick thinks that minimalism or something like it is not a second-best solution at all, that constrained politicization is actually better than neoformalism. Or perhaps, Rick simply chooses to focus his attention and his formidable intellectual skills on the problems at hand—leaving the long-run first-best questions for another day. Rick? Monday, March 10, 2003
New on SSRN Here are some of the new papers on SSRN:
Riz Mokal (University College, London) offers On Fairness and Efficiency. Gary Simson (Cornell) posts School Vouchers and the Constitution - Permissible, Impermissible, or Required?, forthcoming in the Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy. Monday Workshops Here is the roundup:
At the Oxford Centre for Ethics and Philosophy of Law, Jonathan Glover (King's College) presents Dignity and violence: an empirical approach to ethics. And also today, at Oxford, the first day of the Oxford Legal Philosophy Colloquium 2003, includes:
John Gardner and Elisa Holmes (Oxford) deliver Two concepts of law. Samantha Besson (Oxford) gives us Conflicts of rights. Ongoing Debates Department: Political Ideology and Judicial Selection Rick Hasen and I are engaged in an ongoing debate about the role of political ideology in judging. Rick’s latest contribution was made on last Monday. My reply began on Saturday, with a second post on Sunday, and continues today. The Issue How should politics figure in judicial selection? I have argued that the first-best answer to this question is that we should select judges on the basis of their possession of the judicial virtues—especially the virtue of justice, the disposition to decide in accord with the law and not political ideology. Rick has not contested neoformalism as the first best solution—although he has reserved the right to do so. Instead, Rick argues that because the current Supreme Court is (and has been) highly politicized, we should move to a second-best solution, which he calls minimalism. Thus the issue is one of nonideal theory: how should we select judges once politicization has set in? A Game Theoretic Approach A Noniterative Two Person Game One way to conceptualize this issue is from the perspective of game theory. We might imagine this game as a simple two-player prisoners dilemma. Let’s call the two players liberal and conservative. Each player has two options, politicize (appoint political judges) or formalize (appoint formalist judges). Let’s abbreviate L=liberal, C=conservative, P=politicize, F=formalize. So LP=the move where the liberal politicizes, CF=conservative formalizes, and so forth. If this were the standard (symmetrical, noniterative) prisoner’s dilemma, the payoff structure would be as follows: {[LF,CF = L2,C2], [LP,CF = L3,C0], [LF,CP = L0,C3], [LP,CP = L1,C1]} This is the class prisoner’s dilemma. From the liberal’s point of view, if the conservative formalizes, then the best move is to politicize. (Liberal judges will always advance the liberal agenda, but conservative judges will vote liberal for formalist reasons half the time.) If the conservative politicizes, then the liberal’s best move is to politicize—to avoid the situation where the conservative judges always vote liberal and the liberal judges vote conservative half the time for formalist reasons. The payoff structure is symmetrical, so both players will politicize. (By the way, Joseph Isenbergh recently made a similar point in his paper Activist Judges Vote Twice.) Complexities Of course, the two person, noniterative model does not capture all of the complexities. A more realistic model would need to account for at least the following:
--Nomination and confirmation interact to produce judges. In an extended model, either the President or Congress could be liberal or conservative. Presidents could politicize or formalize at the nomination stage, and Congress can either confirm or not confirm nominees based either their status as formalist or political, and if political, then their status as conservative or liberal. --The decisional dispositions of judges actually vary on a spectrum, from very conservative to very liberal, and from very formalist to very political. Tit for Tat Here is one possible lesson of a game-theoretic approach to judicial selection. Suppose that you are playing the judicial-selection game. The other side has moved first, appointing political judges. It is now your turn. Perhaps, you believe the first-best outcome is the rule of law. But if your move is to formalize, you get the worst of both worlds. There are too many political judges for the rule of law to prevail, but the formalist judges you appoint will sometimes vote with your opponent’s judges for formalist reasons. You don’t get the rule of law, and you don’t get the outcome you want. Now, it is possible that if your move this turn is to formalize, then your opponent will cooperate and also formalize when your opponent controls the selection process. But given that your opponent defected during the last round, you have no basis for trusting your opponent. Experiments using iterative versions of the prisoner’s dilemma game, suggest that the best strategy is tit for tat. If your opponent defects in round one, then you defect in round two. If your opponent then cooperates in round three, you cooperate in round four. If you play tit for tat, your player will eventually see the pattern, and begin to cooperate. I Have Good News and Bad News What are the implications of our informal game-theoric analysis of judicial selection? There is good news and there is bad news. The Good News First Here is the good news. If the rule of law really is a better outcome than a downward spiral of politicization, then, in theory and over the long run, it should be possible for a cooperative equilibrium to emerge. That is, liberals and conservatives should both appoint formalist judges. Tit for tat should lead to cooperation. Now the Bad News If Rick Hasen is right, however, we have already spiraled down to the point where a cooperative strategy is, in Rick’s words, “totally unrealistic.” Why? What explains the failure to cooperate? In the actual world, of course, there are historical explanations. We can, however, give a game-theoretical explanation, focusing one two factors, asymmetric perceptions and short sightedness. Asymmetric Perceptions For a variety of reasons, a downward spiral could develop. Cooperation requires trust, but the strife associated with partisan politics may undermine the basis for trust. In particular, each side is likely to perceive the other side’s judges as more political than would a neutral third party. Similarly, each side is more likely to perceive its judges as more neutral than would a neutral observer. Thus, both liberal and conservatives might simultaneously assert, “Our judges are only a little political, but yours are very political.” Given asymmetrical perceptions, it is possible that each side would characterize the same round of play as, “We cooperated, but they defected.” Leading in the next round to deliberate defection by both sides. Short Sightedness The problem of asymmetrical perceptions can be exacerbated by another phenomenon, short sightedness. For a variety of reasons, one side or the other may apply a very high discount rate to payoffs beyond the current round of play. For example, one side may perceive that its electoral chances depend on the appointment of judges who are committed to outcomes on particular issues. Incumbents may not care about outcomes past the current round if they will no longer be playing. More simply, intense partisan strife may produce an irrational preoccupation with winning in the current round of play. Short-sightedness may result in one side or the other defecting from the cooperative strategy. Downward Spiral The combination of short sightedness and asymmetrical perceptions could result in a downward spiral. If the spiral persists for several rounds of play, then both sides could rationally come to believe that a stable cooperative equilibrium is impossible. Under these circumstances, then the tit-for-tat strategy might give way to a doubling-up strategy. Each side might attempt to recoup its loses by doubling the bet—in other words, by appointing judges who are even more ideological and whose views are more extreme. This would accelerate the progression of the downward spiral. How to Escape the Downward Spiral Tomorrow, I will suggest options for converting a downward spiral into a stable cooperative equilibrium. In other words, I will suggest how we might begin to transform a judicial selection process that is dominated by political ideology into a process that focuses on selection on the basis of judicial virtue. Tune in Tomorrow. Same Bat Time. Same Bat Channel. Sunday, March 09, 2003
Ongoing Debates Department: Political Ideology and Judicial Selection Yesterday, I posted the first part of my reply to Rick Hasen’s recent thoughts on politics and judging—Rick’s post is here . Minimalism versus Neoformalism Rick argued that my position, neoformalism (prior post here), is unrealistic. In election law cases (maybe all cases), judges will decide politically, so even if the rule of law is the first best solution, the expectation that judges will adhere to the rule of law is utopian. Rick argues that his position, minimalism, is the second best. Boys will be boys, and judges will be political. The best we can hope for with respect to politicized judging that is be reasonably constrained. Thus, Rick has me backed into a corner. If Rick is right, his position is realistic, and for that reason it can actually make things better. My position, that we ought to select judges who possess the virtue of justice—the disposition to adjudicate on the basis of law rather than political preferences—is utopian, at least, so Rick says. (For a developed statement of my position, jump to the download page here.) Moving in a neoformalist direction wouldn’t work and might actually make things worse. Second Best Rick’s argument depends on a simple but important idea—the notion of the second best. The notion of the second best was developed in R.G. Lipsey & Kelvin Lancaster’s famous article, The General Theory of the Second Best, 24 Review of Economic Studies 11 (1956). The very general idea of the theory of the second best can be expressed as follows:
The Possibilities It is not quite clear from Rick’s posts what answers Rick would give to my questions. This is quite understandable. We are, after all, blogging—not writing a series of law review articles. So consider two possibilities:
First, Rick hasn’t produced any arguments for this proposition. Second, the experience of other legal cultures with constrained judiciaries suggests that judges can decide according to law. (Rick and I can argue about examples if he wishes to press this point.) Third, it seems unlikely that there is any inherent feature of human psychology that would preclude judges from deciding according to law. Let’s rule out Possibility One for now. We can come back to it, if this is Rick tells us that this is what he meant. Possibility Two. Perhaps, then Rick is arguing that it is the current set of Supreme Court Justices that lack the virtue of justice. If all the members of the current court suffer from the vice of results-orientation, then neoformalism is not a realistic option. If this is what Rick means, then I mostly agree with him. The court is politicized, and it would be difficult for the court to transform itself into an apolitical, rule-of-law oriented institution. It would certainly be difficult for this to happen all at once—a neoformalist “big bang” does seem unrealistic. Non-Ideal Theory At this point, the issue is joined as a problem of non-ideal theory. Rick has reserved the right to contest my claim that the ideal system has judges with the virtue of justice, who decide according to law and not politics, but for now our disagreement focuses on a particular situation. How should we select judges when the judiciary (particularly the highest tribunal) has been thoroughly politicized? Rick and I share an important belief about this situation. It is not in equilibrium. Rick stated his worry by referring to “mutually assured destruction,” whereas I put the point by stating that “the rule of law is fragile.” We both believe that full-tilt, unconstrained politicization could lead to an undesirable state of affairs. So what should we do? Should we try to move toward first best? Should we attempt to stabilize the status quo? Should we try for a marginal improvement? Or are we doomed to a downward spiral of ever increasing politicization? This is a fascinating topic, and it will be the subject of my next post in this series. Tune in on Monday. Same Bat Time. Same Bat Channel. Saturday, March 08, 2003
Betram on Commodification The ever interesting Chris Betram (Junius) has a really nice post on commodification. Chris notes that there are several commodification issues upon which opinion divides in a polar fashion:
Respondents seem to break down into three categories: people who think it is just obviously ok, people who think it is just obviously wrong, and people who find themselves switching back and forth between perspectives. Ongoing Debates Department: Political Ideology and Judicial Selection It all started with my post replying to Adam Cohen’s Op Ed attacking Justice Deborah Cook—a Justice of the Ohio Supreme Court nominated to a vacancy on the United States Court of Appeal for the Sixth Circuit. The main point of my reply was to correct distortions in Cohen’s account of Cook’s record—to my knowledge no one has denied that Cohen’s Op Ed was misleading at best. By the way, I have neither endorsed nor opposed Justice Cook. I just don’t know enough about her record to answer the relevant question: does she possess the judicial virtues? Is she a judge with deep knowledge of the law, practical wisdom, courage, and integrity? Most importantly, does she have the virtue of justice—the disposition to decide cases in accord with the law and not her personal political ideology? Adam Cohen’s Op Ed suggested that the relevant question was whether she tended to vote for big business or the little guy—irrespective of the legal merits. It was my reply to that aspect of Cohen's editorial that sparked my ongoing debate with Rick Hasen. What Role Should Political Ideology Play in Judicial Selection? Here is what I wrote:
Rick's Latest Move Rick has replied in a very thoughtful and eloquent post which I urge you to read. Here is the link. The gist of Rick's argument is:
What's Going On So what is going on here? Let me step out of role for a moment. The debate between Rick Hasen and myself falls into a classic pattern. We start with a particularized disagreement. In this case, I argued that opposition to Justice Cook on the basis of political ideology was wrong as a matter of political morality, whereas Rick believes that such opposition is appropriate. Rick then took me on. His reply was effective, because he used hypotheticals very cleverly, showing that my theoretical positon, neoformalism, leads to consequences that both liberals and conservatives wouldn't like--liberals cannot swallow the poll tax and conservatives have a similar intolerance for Roe v. Wade. My countermove was conceptual ascent. I moved the debate off Judge Cook and the current political scene and onto my turf--jurisprudence and abstract legal theory. Rick's latest reply is to move in the opposite direction. Rick is the master of the particular. When it comes to the Supreme Court's election law cases, hardly anyone is in the same league. If I were to get into the details of the caselaw, and attempt to show that there are principled justifications for the Supreme Court's election law decisions, Rick would trounce me. Rick's latest post ran away from my claims about general jurisprudence. And you guess what I am going to do next. I am going to run away from election law. I need to find a hook in Rick's argument that allows me to play the game of confession and avoidance. Yes, Rick, you are right about the election law cases, but . . . The Crucial Move So here is the crucial move. Of course, you can't beat a normative theory with a bunch of cases. As Richard Epstein famously said, "It takes a theory to be a theory." (My post on this aphorism is here.) Rick knows this. He had to make a theoretical countermove. Here it is:
What do I do now? So how do I get out of this? If I just retreat to the abstract theoretical debate, Rick wins the argument that he wants to win. If I descend to the level of particular cases, I will need to shift from election law to some other topic on which I have a knowledge edge (I would go to prior adjudication, where I wrote the book.) But at best, that would result in a tie. At worst, Rick still wins, because he can say, "In the really important cases, the law is now irredeemably political." Damn. Rick Has Forced My Next Move There is only one way out. I need to take on Rick's argument that we should forgo discussion of first-best solutions (the virtue of justice and the rule of law) and move to second best solutions (minimalist political judging). Tomorrow, the debate continues. Tune in on Sunday. Same Bat Time. Same Bat Channel. Rorty on Quine If you are interested in contemporary philosphy and its post-WWII history, you will want to read Richard Rorty's essay Analytic Philosophy and Transformative Philosophy. Here is a little nibble:
Friday, March 07, 2003
Catching Up with Alon Harel on Judicial Review Alon Harel (Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Felt Center for Legal Studies & Harvard, Center for Ethics and the Professions) posted Rights-Based Judicial Review: A Democratic Justification on SSRN a while back & I have just caught up with Alon's very fine paper. Unfortunately, Alon has turned on the copy defeat mechanism in the .pdf file & I can't give you the juicy quotes, but here is the abstract:
New on SSRN Here is what's new on SSRN:
Lance Lochner (Stanford, Hoover Institution) uploads Perceptions of the Criminal Justice System.
Lawrence Cunningham (Boston College) posts Semiotics, Hermeneutics and Cash: An Essay on the True and Fair View, forthcoming in the North Carolina Journal of International Law and Commercial Regulation. My colleague Rick Hasen has uploaded Leaving the Empty Vessel of "Republicanism" Unfilled: An Argument for the Continued Non-Justiciability of Guarantee Clause Cases. I have been thinking about the Guarantee Clause quite a bit lately. I'll post on Rick's paper in a few days. Friday's Workshops Here is the roundup for today:
At Loyola Marymount, Karl Manheim (Loyola Marymount) and Lawrence Solum (San Diego, Visiting & Loyola Marymount) present gTLD Auctions: Formulating Policy for the Domain Name System. Here is a taste of our paper:
Thursday, March 06, 2003
War, Evolutionary Biology, Decision Theory, and the Psychology of Bluffing Via Arts & Letters Daily, the Telegraph has an interesting piece by Raj Persaud on the psychology of bluffing. Persaud speculates on its role in war. Here is a taste:
Hmm. Isn't correction for this sort of error the full time job of a whole lot of people? Thursday is Workshop Day Here is the weekly roundup of Thursday workshops and colloquia from around the world:
At the University of San Diego, there are two workshops:
Alan Schwartz (Yale) does Understanding MACs and MAEs. At Yale's Legal Theory Workshop, Joanne Freeman (Yale, History) presents The Field of Blood. Freeman's paper is fascinating. It's subject is violent behavior by members of Congress. Here is a taste:
Boston University presents Peter Berkowitz (George Mason & Hoover) with The Lawfulness of the Election Decision: A Reply to Professor Tribe, coauthored with Benjamin Wittes of the Washington Post. Thanks to David Petron for the link & information about the coauthor. Just War Theory This is an opinionated but not particularly political blog. The blogosphere is a strange land for me, because so many of the blogs that I admire are very political. And the political issue of the day is the war. So I was relieved when I thought of a way to post on the war that was in the spirit of Legal Theory Blog. My taking off point is a piece by Peter Steinfels in the New York Times, entitled Meeting a Moral Standard for War. The focal point is Michael Walzer's famous book on just war theory--really the starting point for contemporary legal and political thought about a topic for which the locus classicus is Aquinas. Stienfels writes:
But There Is Another Crucial Dimension to the Issue And you won't like what I am about to say. I don't like it much myself. I am about to say something about authority. And I'm not going to say "Question Authority!" Yes, Walzer is right. Sound practical judgment is required to apply the last-resort criterion for a just war, but it is highly unlikely (no, it is just plain impossible) that each and every citizen's judgment will agree on the question as to whether the criterion has been met. Even if we all acted in complete good faith, even if we all had access to all the information, even if we were all pretty darn smart, we still wouldn't agree. We live in a pluralist democracy. We have different world views, different religions, we adhere to a variety of what John Rawls called "comprehensive conceptions of the good." Not only is unanimity impossible, even consensus is impossible if each citizen uses her own practical reason to answer the question, "Have we exhausted the alternatives to war?" So consensus in private judgment cannot be what is required. Public and not private reason must resolve this question. And in this case, public reason is specified by authority. See! I told you that you wouldn't like it. This argument goes way back. It is Hobbes's argument. And his systematic development of the argument against the authority of private reason is the core of the greatest work in the history of political philosophy--Leviathan. And in this case, Hobbes is right. But What About Vietnam? Good question! Exactly the right question. Let me generalize it. What about the case where your private judgment tells you that authoritative public reason has made the wrong call? Shouldn't you protest? Go to Canada? Plant a bomb in an ROTC office? Here is what I wish I could produce. I wish that I could give you a knock down, crystal clear, self-applying, intersubjectively shareable, and definite set of criteria that would provide guidance where guidance is needed. Protest these wars, but respect public reason on those wars! Wouldn't it be nice? But it isn't available. Just as the last-resort criterion in just-war theory requires sound practical judgment, so practical judgment is required when we make the decision not to defer to public reason and stick to our private judgments about our nation's wars. You May Think It Is Easy Whether you support the war or oppose it, you may think the judgment call is easy. If you oppose war with Iraq, I imagine that deep down you believe some of the things on this list: (1) the President isn't smart enough to make this decision; (2) the real purpose of the war would be to control Iraq's oil; (3) the real purpose of the war is personal hatred by the President of Saddam Hussein; (4) our national leadership is arrogant and ill-informed. If you suport the war, I think you are likely to believe some of the things on this list: (1) opponents of the war are utopian pacifists who wouldn't support any war, even against the Nazis or Stalin; (2) opponents of the war are ill informed and deluded by Iraqi propaganda; (3) opponents of the war hate America; (4) opponents of the war are motivated by the desire to undermine the President politically and would have supported the war if initiated by the prior administration. I don't believe any of the statements on either list. The fact that such beliefs are common is symptomatic of an unhealthy civic culture, a loss of mutual trust and respect, and the scarcity of the virtue of civility. A Civil Discourse About the War I have no crystal ball and I am not an instapundit. But I think war is coming. How will we react as a nation? Will we rally round the flag in blind and unthinking patriotism. Will there be bitter and acrimonious debate? I don't know what will happen, but I do know that for which I hope. I hope for respectful civil discourse. I hope for more light than heat. I hope for more reason than passion. I hope for citizenship and not partisanship. Ok, ok, enough with the platitudes. Here comes the hard part. And I hope for respect for the authority of public reason. Resources on Just War Theory Here are some just-war theory resources on the Web:
:: There is an entry titled Just War Theory in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy :: Another collection of links. :: Alexander Moeser's paper Just War Theory in a Changing World. Wednesday, March 05, 2003
Has Bernard Williams Joined the Frankfurt School? I've just had a chance to read Bernard Williams's paper (presented at University College today and downloadable here), a teaser for which I posted earlier today. The central new idea of the paper is called by Williams The Critical Principle. Here is his statement of the principle itself:
Plug The workshop paper is a chapter from Williams's book Truth and Truthfulness. I highly recommend the chapter, especially to those who missed out on the intense but brief reception of Frankfurt-school style critical theory by Anglo-American legal theory in the 1980s. Isn’t Critical Theory Old Hat? Well, yes. The CLS wars resulted in a general (not universal) rejection of the Frankfurt school by the legal academy, with some residual support for Habermas. But my judgment is that important things were learned from this encounter. I would guess that most theoretically inclined law students and junior law faculty members are unlikely to have read their Habermas, much less their Marcuse and Adorno. Time is precious, but some exposure to the Frankfurt school’s synthesis of Marx and Weber is essential to understanding the late twentieth century movement of legal thought. Ideas bantered at faculty lunch tables and workshops every day originated with the Frankfurt school. Habermas, Marcuse, and Adorno influenced critical legal studies which in turn set the stage for feminist jurisprudence and critical race theory—ideas that are important parts of the mix that constitutes one of the dominant styles of contemporary legal theory—eclectic left neorealism. Reports, Anyone? If you were there for the real thing, live, with Ronnie Dworkin going at Bernard Williams, email! Recent Uploads Department Nathan Oman (A Good Oman, oh, and also Harvard Law Review) uploads Statutory Interpetation in Econotopia. Here is a taste of Nathan's very interesting paper:
Wednesday's Workshops There are some absolutely terrific workshops today. Here is the roundup:
At Florida State, Alfred R. Mele (Florida State, Philosophy) workshops Acting Intentionally: Probing Folk Notions. At the University of Texas, Brian Leiter's Law and Philosophy Program has Gerry Cohen (All Souls) both today and tomorrow.
Tuesday, March 04, 2003
New Today on SSRN Vincy Fon (George Washington, Economics) and Francesco Parisi (George Mason, Law) post The Limits of Reciprocity for Social Cooperation. And while you are at it, check out Dan Kahan's very interesting The Logic of Reciprocity: Trust, Collective Action, and Law. The Pledge of Alliegiance The whole crew at the Volokh Counterhegemonic Blog Enclave is getting into the pledge of alliegance controversy. Posts by Eugene (the counterhegemon himself), also here and here, Jacob Levy, and Philippe de Croy. And there is a wonderful post by Jack Balkin over on Balkinization. Breaking News: The panel decision has been stayed according to AP courtesy of How Appealling Update: There is another nice post on the pledge over at Greg Goelzhauser.. By The Way . . . BTW, it is a sign of the times that a google search for the exact phrase "counterhegemonic enclave" produces only one hit! Could this be the start of a new version of googlewhack? What once in vogue ideas from legal theory now produce exactly one hit when googled? Ongoing Debates Department: Political Ideology and Judging Rick Hasen replies to my Sunday post. Great Ceasar's Ghost! It's back to the drawing board for me. Watch this department for further developments later in the week. New On SSRN Here is today's roundup:
Vasan Kesavan and Michael Paulsen (Minnesota) post Is West Virginia Unconstitutional? forthcoming in the California Law Review. Alexander Somek (Institute for Legal Philosophy and Legal Theory) uploads Legal Formality and Freedom of Choice. A Moral Perspective on Jhering's Constructivism forthcoming in Ratio Juris. And by the way check out the Institute's Vienna Working Papers in Legal Theory, Political Philosophy, and Applied Ethics Martin Golding (Duke) digitalizes The Cultural Defense forthcoming in Ratio Juris Tuesday Workshops Here is today's roundup:
Blanca Rodriguez Ruez presents Ethic of Care and Constitutional Law at Oxford's jurisprudence discussion group. LOL I did. And you will too, if you hop over to economist Brad DeLong's post of an except from Poundstone's Prisoner's Dilemma. Armen Alchian of UCLA plays RAND's John D. Williams in an iterative asymetrical-payoff variation on the classic game, and each recorded their reactions to the other's play. Courtesy of the always excellent Junius. Monday, March 03, 2003
Oxford Legal Philosophy Colloquium 2003 John Gardner (Oxford) emails this morning re the Oxford Legal Philosophy Colloquium 2003. Here are some of the details that John provided:
in association with the Oxford Centre for Ethics and Philosophy of Law Our 2003 Colloquium takes place on 10 and 11 March 2003. It is open to everyone at no charge (there may be a nominal on-the-spot charge for lunches). Please note that that each day's proceedings are at a different venue. Visit http://www.law.ox.ac.uk/jurisprudence/colloquium03.htm to download papers as they become available, and to keep an eye out for programme changes. Workshops Today Here is the roundup:
Frederick Schauer (Harvard, Kennedy School) presents The Boundaries of The First Amendment: A Preliminary Exploration of Constitutional Salience at Georgetown's Constitutional Theory series. Nick Zangwill (Oxford) does 'Supervenience and moral epistemology' at the Oxford Centre for Ethics and Philosophy of Law. New on SSRN Here is this morning's roundup of what's new and interesting on SSRN:
Paddy Hillyard (University of Ulster at Jordanstown) uploads Invoking Indignation: Reflections on Future Directions of Socio–legal Studies (appearing in the Journal of Law and Society). Roger Cotterrell (University of London)gives us Subverting Orthodoxy, Making Law Central: A View of Sociolegal Studies (appearing in the Journal of Law and Society). Daphne Barak-Erez (Tel-Aviv University) shares Judicial Review of Politics: The Israeli Case (appearing in the Journal of Law and Society). Sunday, March 02, 2003
Ongoing Debates Department: Hasen on the Role of Ideology in Judicial Selection This all got started with my post on Adam Cohen's Op/Ed attacking Barbara Cook. The main point of my post concerned the inaccuracies in Cohen's piece, but I also said:
My colleague Rick Hasen posted a reply that argued: we already
live in an era of both liberal and conservative judicial activism. We have a
judiciary that is just another political branch. And I responded:
Rick is unduly pessimistic about
the possibility of realizing or restoring the rule of law. And if Rick is right that the judiciary is
irretrievably politicized: Why have nine unelected individuals
as a council of review? Now Rick replies
again: Fair enough, and scholars like Mark
Tushnet have made the argument against judicial review along precisely these
lines. As for whether "text, original meaning and the doctrine of stare
decisis" are significant constraints, consider the following two questions
to be determined by the new Supreme Court Justice applying neutral principles:
Egads, hypos! I became a law professor so I wouldn't
have to answer these ever again. On the tough questions, I just
don't see text, original meaning, and the doctrine of stare decisis as either
dispositive or necessarily the only correct bases upon which to decide such
cases. Such decisions are inherently political. It would be unfair to pin Rick down to a general
jurisprudence based on these remarks. (So, he has plenty of wiggle room.) But,
it looks like Rick's position is a very familiar one. He is a neorealist or
neoinstrumentalist. When he says "as either dispositive," I think he
is making a descriptive claim--that existing legal materials do not determine
the outcome of the case as a matter of the constituitive conventions that
specify what can count as a correct legal outcome. When Rick says "the
only correct bases upon which to decide cases," I think he is making a
normative claim--that, even if the legal materials could resolve the case, it
doesn't follow that they should resolve the case. And when he says:
"Such decisions are inherently political," he is moving close to the
central thesis of critical legal studies: Law is Politics! Of course,
that is precisely the position that I am arguing is neither necessary (as a
matter of fact) nor desirable (as a matter of political and legal philosophy.) I believe there are ways for the
Supreme Court to constrain itself, as developed in my book. The arguments
depend upon both liberal and conservative activists pulling back from the brink
of mutually assured destruction through writing more minimalist decisions. I think I agree, but I am not sure. What is a minimalist
decision? Consider three possibilities: 1. Minimialist decisions are
decisions that that hew closely to the requirements of law. In the case, Rick
and I are in agreement--at least with respect to election-law cases. Undoubtedly, I haven't done justice to Rick's true position.
But however he formulates minimalism, I think it is fair for me to throw Roe
v. Wade back at him. What is the minimalist position in Roe? Saturday, March 01, 2003
The Debate The last event at the Stanford Spectrum conference was a debate. Larry Lessig (Stanford) and Yochai Benkler (NYU) advocated a commons approach to spectrum allocation. Gerald R. Faulhaber (Wharton) and Thomas Hazlett (Manhattan Institute) advocated a property approach. The judges were Alex Kozinski, Harold Demsetz (Economics, UCLA) and nobel laureate Vernon Smith (Economics, George Mason). It was good fun, although this is one of the few moot courts where Kozinski did not take over. Perhaps Alex thought it would be interesting to see what the economists had to say. Why this is important It all goes back to Coase, of course. His famous 1959 article on the Federal Communications Commission made an intellectually compelling argument against FCC regulation of broadcasting. Give it to the market! But since 1959, broadcasting technology has changed. With spread spectrum and frequency hopping technologies, it is possible for multiple users and services to share the same spectrum. It is no longer clear that bandwidth chunks represent the efficient form of utilization for the spectrum space. Ah, you immediately see where this going. Coase again! Why won't the market reach the optimal allocation? Spectrum owners will just trade to optimum. And you can already guess what Lessig and Benkler said in response. Transaction costs. If the spectrum is divided among hundreds or thousands of players, it may be quite difficult to make a market that will reallocate the spectrum at costs lower than a commons. And I'll bet you know what comes next. A commons isn't really a free for all. Etiquette or protocols that eliminate interference need to be negotiated, or some users will hold others hostage with interfering uses. So there will be transaction costs with a commons regime as well. Which system will more efficiently reach the optimum? No one had a knock down argument. Barnett's Important Observaton Randy Barnett (Boston University) watched the live feed, and has this very important observation. This wasn't really commons versus property. It was property versus property. The real competition is between two different property regimes. One regime grants rights to the owners of devices (phones, wifi cards, and relay stations) to use their property free from interference. This model emphasizes control over physical resources. The other regime has the government grant a right to "spectrum owners' to stop the use of devices by owners. The model emphasizes control over the spectrum. These are both property regimes. Lessig wants to call the first of these two regimes a commons, but that is completely misleading. In fact, the first regime is the traditonal property rights regime, with the least government interference in the market. The second regime is a nontraditional property rights regime; with government interfering with traditional property to create new kinds of property rights. Most of the audience and propably the members of the panel thought that the "property side" won. But if you listened very carefully to Smith and Demsetz, it sounded to me like they had moved very close to the traditional property model. This was, in substance, but not in form, the Lessig/Benkler position. Read Barnett's Reds in Suits to get a sense of his position on the analagous property versus property analysis of debates over intellectual property rights. And one more thing . . . Yochai is one smart dude. Commons versus Property The Spectrum conference today at Stanford has been fascinating. The conference was framed in terms of a debate between two options for spectrum policy. The first is a property regime, essentially to auction off the spectrum. Evan Kwerel & John Williams presented their paper entitled A Proposal for Rapid Transition to Market Allocation of Spectrum. The other approach, championed by Larry Lessig and others, is to create a commons. What about interference? New technologies may allow multiple broadcasters to use simultaneously occupy the same spectrum slice (or to hop between slices). No one defended the "beauty contest" approach to spectrum allocation that prevailed for the first several decades of broadcast regulation, with the FCC making case-by-case public interest determinations as to which uses are the best uses. One theme that emerged from several of the comments is that the choice between property and commons need not be binary; both models may exist side by side. Junius Is One Today Chris Betram's excellent blog Junius (and permanent link on the sidebar) is one today. I began blogging very tentatively, quite unsure of the demand for a blog that focused on legal theory. Junius is one of the blogs that convinced me to continue. It offers thoughtful, interesting, well-crafted posts on a variety of topics of real intellectual interest. Thank you, Chris. Blogging from Stanford Today Today, I am blogging from the Spectrum Policy: Property or Commons at Stanford. Internet access may be difficult, so there may be one big post at the end of the day. Google Problem: Google has been sending you to the February Archive of Legal Theory Blog. To get to the latest posts, click here. |