Legal Theory Blog



All the theory that fits!

Home

This is Lawrence Solum's legal theory weblog. Legal Theory Blog comments and reports on recent scholarship in jurisprudence, law and philosophy, law and economic theory, and theoretical work in substantive areas, such as constitutional law, cyberlaw, procedure, criminal law, intellectual property, torts, contracts, etc.

RSS
This page is powered by Blogger. Isn't yours?
Tuesday, January 31, 2006
 
Hasen on the Failure of the Alito Filibuster Read The Failed Alito Filibuster, with an excellent analysis of Hasen's own failed prediction that Alito would be defeated. Here's a taste:
    Where does this leave Democrats? Thought the "Gang of 14" agreement has saved the Senate from the nuclear option, it has seriously weakened the Democrats, who apparently won't be able to block any competent Bush nominee to the Supreme Court (should another nomination open up). It may still be possible to block lower stakes judicial nominees, as is apparently happening with DC Circuit nominee Brett Kavanaugh.
Just another thought or two:
    With respect to overruling Roe, I think it is important to remember that Alito is at most the fourth vote, and that assumes that Roberts was the third, which is not at all clear yet.
    With respect to the Gang of 14 and the agreement, I certainly agree that the agreement did not help Democrats or hurt Republicans--contrary to the hew and cry at the time. But I don't think the agreement itself, actually hurts Democrats much either. It is not the agreement among the Gang of 14 that prevents a successful filibuster. That's because the agreement is not much more than "cheap talk." Any Senator who wanted to vote against Alito could reasonably claim exceptional circumstances. It is the political preferences of the Senators and not the agreement or the chumminess of the gang that is doing the work.
Read Rick's post!


 
Rowe & Baskauskas on the Rooker-Feldman Doctrine Thomas D. Rowe, Jr. and Edward L. Baskauskas (Duke University School of Law and Golden Gate University - School of Law) have posted 'Inextricably Intertwined' Explicable at Last? Rooker-Feldman Analysis After the Supreme Court's Exxon Mobil Decision (Federal Courts Law Review, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    The Supreme Court's March 2005 decision in 'Exxon Mobil Corp. v. Saudi Basic Industries Corp.' substantially limited the Rooker-Feldman doctrine, under which lower federal courts largely lack jurisdiction to engage in what amounts to de facto review of state-court decisions. Exxon Mobil's holding is quite narrow - entry of a final state-court judgment does not destroy federal-court jurisdiction already acquired over parallel litigation. But the Court's articulation of when Rooker-Feldman applies, and its approach in deciding the case, have significant implications for several aspects of Rooker-Feldman jurisprudence. Chief among our claims is that although the Court did not expressly repudiate or limit the applicability of the inextricably intertwined formulation from prior cases, which had been a primary test for many lower courts, that concept appears to have been relegated to some secondary role and no longer to be a general or threshold test. The Exxon Mobil Court properly did not elaborate on just what the concept's role should be, but we offer a suggestion based on an earlier Ninth Circuit decision. We also discuss the apparent impact of Exxon Mobil on other aspects of Rooker-Feldman doctrine as the lower federal courts had developed it, including relation to preclusion doctrines, the significance of whether the federal plaintiff was plaintiff or defendant in state court, and the doctrine's applicability a) to those not parties to prior state-court litigation, b) to interlocutory state-court rulings and decisions of lower state courts, and c) when federal-court plaintiffs did not raise their federal claims in state court.


 
Tuesday Calendar
    Marquette Law: Eric Goldman, Marquette University Law School, Placing and Marketing Scholarship


 
Comande on Adjudicating Personal Injury Damages Giovanni Comande (Sant'Anna School of Advanced Studies - Faculty of Law) has posted Towards a Global Model for Adjudicating Personal Injury Damages: Bridging Europe and the United States (Temple International & Comparative Law Journal, Vol. 19, No. 2, 2005) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    Techniques for awarding personal injury damages assume an increasing interest in times of frequent mobility of individuals. Assessing non-economic damages might require more harmonized answers to provide justice and equal treatment across the world. Indeed, in most countries a lasting debate surrounds noneconomic damages for personal injury. Specifically, an alleged constant increase in awards and the difficulties linked to the subjectivity of their assessment, and the selection of the institution that is best suited to award these damages and how it should do so are but a few problems that are addressed by contemporary scholarship. However, this extensive debate has not sufficiently explored the techniques for awarding intangible loss damages in personal injury by using a comparative law methodology. Filling this gap, this article explores the latest developments in awarding noneconomic damages. It further proposes an analysis of the American and European experiences which aims to bridge these two legal cultures for mutual benefit. By way of comparative and historical analysis, Part I highlights the significant trend in American and European jurisdictions, which consists of distinguishing non-economic damages based on objective criteria stemming from an ascertainable medical condition. Building on these results, Parts II and III develop a more efficient conceptual framework and further propose better assessment tools in awarding these damages. This method demonstrates the benefits the United.States could gain by introducing innovative judicial scheduling, without triggering either constitutional concerns or statutory intervention while building upon the existing strengths of the European experience and the American judicial system. For instance, Normalized Value Scheduling would endow actual judges and jurors with the necessary expertise, increasing horizontal and vertical equality without necessarily impeding an inevitable variability of awards among different jurisdictions.


 
McGovern on Claims Resolution Faciliites Francis E. McGovern (Duke University School of Law) has posted The What and Why of Claims Resolution Facilities (Stanford Law Review, Vol. 57, p. 1361, April 2005) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    Claims resolution facility is a generic term used to describe a wide range of entities that process and resolve claims made against a potential funding source. In the context of a natural disaster, for example, there might be facilities to process claims based upon insurance policies, federal or state statutory or administrative rights, international relief efforts, contractual obligations, or any *1362 other basis for receiving economic or noneconomic benefits. These facilities are generally characterized by a large number of claims that are in need of rapid and efficient resolution. In certain instances, however, the positive connotations of the term have been expropriated to describe a facility that desires to appear quick and efficient while acting slowly and expensively. In the context of alternatives to the litigation system, claims resolution facilities function to enable the disaggregation of liability from damages in the determination of legal entitlements either individually or collectively, in settlement or as a precursor to litigation. The facilities operate under the assumption that there is at least some liability, and their role is to focus on any residual damage issues not resolved through litigation or settlement. These facilities vary considerably in form, from qualified settlement funds recognized by the federal tax code to ad hoc efforts to resolve disputes prior to any invocation of the legal system. In the context of a man-made disaster, for example, there might be facilities either by defendants or their insurance carriers to settle claims prior to the intervention of attorneys, to evaluate and/or settle claims individually or in groups after the retention of counsel either before or after the initiation of litigation, to determine individual or collective damages, or to allocate damages among claimants. Part I attempts to identify the critical variables that are integral to the claims resolution facilities that have become alternatives to traditional litigation. These variables include all the essential elements, with particular attention to the criteria and methodology used by claims resolution facilities to evaluate, process, and pay claims. In Part II, there is an analysis of the strategy for designing a claims resolution facility that takes advantage of the multiplicity of options in order to accommodate the particular needs associated with a given claims resolution facility. Parts III and IV consider the assets and defects of claims resolution facilities, including rationales for their recent popularity. Finally, Part V assesses the future by focusing on common failure modes for claims resolution facilities and then proposes possible substantive standards and procedural rules that may increase the legitimacy of claims resolution facilities.


 
Rosenthal on the Theory of Government Damages Liability Lawrence Rosenthal (Chapman University - School of Law) has posted The Theory and Practice of Government Damages Liability: Torts, Constitutional Torts, and Takings. Here is the abstract:
    Theories of tort liability generally fall within two broad camps: the instrumentalists claim that tort liability promotes efficient investments in safety by cutting into the revenues of those who under-invest in safety; and the advocates of corrective justice claim that tort liability embodies a moral obligation of culpable parties to bear losses for which they are fairly considered responsible. Neither theory offers much support for government tort liability. Unlike private tortfeasors, the government's objective is not profit maximization; it responds to political and not market discipline. Thus, the instrumental justification for tort liability is wanting in the public sector. As for corrective justice, the government passes its legal costs along to the taxpayers, who bear little if any culpability for the underlying tortious conduct. Thus, corrective justice also supplies little support for public-sector tort liability. Indeed, there is an emerging consensus among legal scholars that government tort liability lacks a coherent justification. In this work in progress, I endeavor to show that the emerging consensus is wrong. To do so, I anchor the justification for government tort liability in a theory of political behavior. I look to politics because the government responds primarily to political costs and benefits, whereas private tortfeasors respond primarily to economic rewards or punishment. In my view, government tort liability exacts a political price by diverting the funds used to pay judgments and other litigation costs from what elected officials regard as the politically optimal use of those funds. Therefore, government liability creates a political incentive to invest in loss prevention in order to maximize political control over public resources. This theory, however, does not argue for unlimited government liability; to the contrary, it also provide a justification for many of the immunities that limit government liability.


Monday, January 30, 2006
 
Constitutional Abstraction and Originalism I've been thinking and reading a good deal about constitutional theory recently, and coincidentally have come across several versions of a familiar argument against originalism. It goes something like this:
    The constitution includes abstract and general provisions like the equal proctection clause and the due process clauses of the fifth and fourteenth amendments. The very generality and abstraction of these clauses indicates that they were intended to be interpreted as general principles rather than as particular rules. Therefore, the framers could not have intended that their own intentions about particular issues should guide the process of constitutional interpretation and construction.
It struck me this morning that this argument is horrendously bad--a real stinker, as they say. Consider:
    First, this is an originalist argument. It says that the purpose and public meaning of the general and abstract clauses of the constitution are a guide to how they should be interpreted. This is an originalist move; not an anti-originalist move.
    Second, this argument conflates the crucial distinction between what can be labeled original meaning originalism and original intent originalism. With few exceptions, contemporary originalists believe that the relevant inquiry is into the original public meaning of the constitution--not into the expectaitons or intentions of the framers with respect to how the constitution should or would be applied. Ironically, the move presupposes the relevance of both original public meaning and original intentions as it attempts to argue against them.
    Third, this argument is usually offered without the necessary supporting evidence. The constitution uses the phrase "equal protection of the laws" and "due process of law." Those phrases might be construed as general and abstract principles of equality and fairness, but they might not. Either phrase, or both, might have a relatively particular, sharp edged meaning. Whether they do or not cannot be answered by hand waving. You need to dig into the text and evidence about the public meaning of the phrasss at the time they were drafted and adopted.
    Fourth, the argument does not establish that expectations about application are irrelevant to constructiona and interpretation--merely that they would be relevant in a particular fashion. For example, even if the equal protection clause establishes some kind of equality principle, the question remains, "What principle?" Assume that it is possible that the idea was to establish judicial license to articulate some conception of equality and that the clause embodies only the general concept. (I am deploying the well known concept/conception distinction, best known from Rawls and Dworkin.) Evidence about expectations and intentions would be relevant to the question whether the "concept of equality" was the original public meaning and, if so, what the even the general concept meant.


 
Monday Calendar
    Rutgers-Camden Law: Larence Solum, The Supreme Court in Bondage: Constitutional Stare Decisis, Legal Formalism, and the Future of Unenumerated Rights. See you there!
    UCLA Law: Professor Bill Henderson Indiana University School of Law-Bloomington, "An Empirical Study of Single-Tier versus Two-Tier Partnerships in the AM Law 200"
    Hofstra Law: Seth Harris, New York Law School, “Law, Economics, and Accommodations in the Internal Labor Market”
    NYU Law: Richard Primus.


 
Patterson on Morawetz on Wittgenstein Dennis Patterson (Rutgers University School of Law, Camden) has posted Wittgenstein on Understanding and Interpretation (Comments on the Work of Thomas Morawetz) (Philosophical Investigations, Vol. 29, No. 2, April 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    Wittgenstein’s distinction between understanding and interpretation is fundamental to the account of meaning in Philosophical Investigations. In his discussion of rule-following, Wittgenstein explicitly rejects the idea that understanding or grasping a rule is a matter of interpretation. Wittgenstein explains meaning and rule-following in terms of action, rejecting both realist and Cartesian accounts of the mental. I argue that in his effort to employ Wittgenstein’s views on meaning and rule-following, Professor Morawetz embraces the position Wittgenstein rejects. In the course of making his case for law as a “deliberative practice,” Professor Morawetz embraces interpretation as a fundamental element of human practices, thereby taking up precisely the view Wittgenstein rejects.
I always read Patterson.


 
Garrett & Vermeule on Budget Process Transparency Elizabeth Garrett and Adrian Vermeule (University of Southern California - Law School and University of Chicago Law School) have posted Transparency in the Budget Process on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    Budget procedures are often adopted or changed to improve "transparency" in budgeting. This phrase can refer to two different, although related, stages of the budget process. First, transparency may refer to the outputs of budgeting; here the ideal is that the tradeoffs inherent in a budget should be made clear, salient and understandable to policy makers and the public. Second, transparency may refer to the inputs of budgeting; here the ideal is to ensure that the decision-making process is itself conducted in public. This paper focuses on the second concept of budget transparency - the degree to which important budgeting decisions are made in public and in open deliberation and debate. We identify an ideal transparency regime for the federal budget process, one that optimizes the benefits and costs of transparency and opacity. Two institutional-design tradeoffs are critical. First, transparency allows the public, and others who bring information to the attention of the public such as the media and challengers, to monitor elected officials and hold them accountable. However, it also allows interest groups, whose interests may not be congruent with the larger public interest, to monitor legislators. Because interest groups are better organized than the public, transparency may unduly empower those representing minority interests at the expense of overall welfare. We propose some techniques of transparency - such as delayed disclosure, which provides information some period of time after the budgeting decision has been made - that empower the voters while reducing the ability of interest groups to influence outcomes. Second, we discuss the effect of transparency on legislative arguing and legislative bargaining. Transparency deters self-interested bargains, but can also encourage posturing and inflexibility that produces bad deliberation. We propose that opacity is generally beneficial at earlier stages of the budget process, as where committees develop the macro-level allocations embodied in the concurrent budget resolution, while transparency is desirable at later stages of the process, when committees engage in concrete bargaining. Finally, we discuss various institutional constraints and second-best problems at the implementation stage, including the question whether politics will block adoption of the optimal transparency framework, the risk that transparency will be circumvented by collusion, and the risk that opacity will be undermined by leaks. Although these problems are serious, we conclude that none is insuperable.
A very interesting paper by two of the best.


 
Broughton on Capital Punishment J. Richard Broughton (United States Department of Justice - Capital Case Unit) has posted The Second Death of Capital Punishment on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    This paper seeks to reexamine, and to reformulate, the terms of our national capital punishment dialogue by approaching death penalty jurisprudence as a problem of constitutional structure and form. As a factor contributing to the incremental demise of capital punishment in the United States, omnipotent and omniscient judicial regulation of capital sentencing has significant consequences for the political institutions responsible for controlling the people in our constitutional design. Examining the Supreme Court's recent categorical exemption cases, this paper confronts the raw moral judgments and political preferences that define the Court's immodest understanding of its own authority under the Eighth Amendment. It also examines recent capital habeas cases to demonstrate that the Court may be softening the rigorous standards for habeas relief especially for capital cases. Ultimately, these actions have weakened the death penalty and, more importantly, our political institutions. By serving as a forum for determining which criminal punishments are morally right and desirable, and by compromising the integrity of legal structures that safeguard vital state criminal law interests, the Court diminshes the essential distance that the Constitution places between the government and the governed, and between the institutions that govern. It also undermines the authority of the political branches as the primary institutional mediums for filtering out public passions and building coalitions for responsible democratic action to control the people. The paper therefore urges a greater awareness of, and endorses a constitutional law that safeguards, formal institutional arrangements.


 
Raustiala & Sprigman on the Piracy Paradox and Fashion Design Kal Raustiala and Chris Sprigman (University of California, Los Angeles - School of Law and University of Virginia - School of Law) have posted The Piracy Paradox: Innovation And Intellectual Property In Fashion Design on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    The orthodox justification for intellectual property is utilitarian. Advocates for strong IP rights argue that absent such rights copyists will free-ride on the efforts of creators and stifle innovation. This orthodox justification is logically straightforward and well reflected in the law. Yet a significant empirical anomaly exists: the global fashion industry, which produces a huge variety of creative goods without strong IP protection. Copying is rampant as the orthodox account would predict. Yet innovation and investment remain vibrant. Few commentators have considered the status of fashion design in IP law. Those who have almost uniformly criticize the current legal regime for failing to protect apparel designs. But the fashion industry itself is surprisingly quiescent about copying. Firms take steps to protect the value of trademarks, but appear to accept appropriation of designs as a fact of life. This diffidence about copying stands in striking contrast to the heated condemnation of piracy and associated legislative and litigation campaigns in other creative industries. Why, when other major content industries have obtained increasingly powerful IP protections for their products, does fashion design remain mostly unprotected - and economically successful? The fashion industry is a puzzle for the orthodox justification for IP rights. This paper explores this puzzle. We argue that the fashion industry counter-intuitively operates within a low-IP equilibrium in which copying does not deter innovation and may actually promote it. We call this the “piracy paradox.” This paper offers a model explaining how the fashion industry’s piracy paradox works, and how copying functions as an important element of and perhaps even a necessary predicate to the industry’s swift cycle of innovation. In so doing, we aim to shed light on the creative dynamics of the apparel industry. But we also hope to spark further exploration of a fundamental question of IP policy: to what degree are IP rights necessary to induce innovation? Are stable low-IP equilibria imaginable in other industries as well? Part I describes the fashion industry and its dynamics and illustrates the prevalence of copying in the industry. Part II advances an explanation for the piracy paradox that rests on two features: induced obsolescence and anchoring. Both phenomena reflect the status-conferring power of fashion, and both suggest that copying, rather than impeding innovation and investment, promotes them. Part II also considers, and rejects, alternative explanations of the endurance of the low-IP status quo. Part III considers extensions of our arguments to other fields. By examining copyright's negative space - those creative endeavors that copyright does not address - we argue can we can better understand the relationship between copyright and innovation.


 
Joseph on "Smart Intelligence" Anne M Joseph (UC Berkeley Law) has posted The Architecture of Smart Intelligence: Balancing Unification and Redundancy in Agency Design and Congressional Oversight (California Law Review, Vol. 94, 2006) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    The changes to the intelligence community and its congressional overseers recommended by the 9/11 and WMD Commissions, both those implemented and those not adopted, raise fundamental questions of administrative and constitutional law that cut to the heart of the federal government's effectiveness in addressing two of the most prominent policy imperatives of our time: protecting national security and maintaining core democratic values, including civil liberties, transparency, and accountability. How should agencies and congressional oversight be structured in a system of separated but overlapping powers that aims to protect both national security and central liberal democratic values? Should administrative agencies (or congressional committees) be unified or placed in competition with each other? Answers to these questions are constrained by political realities. As Terry Moe explains, The bureaucracy arises out of politics, and its design reflects the interests, strategies, and compromises of those who exercise political power. Drawing on research in economics, political science, and law, this paper considers three important perspectives on the recommendations to unify intelligence agencies and to consolidate congressional oversight, which have not, so far as I can tell, been applied to intelligence reform rigorously in combination. These perspectives, in addition, have wider application to any possible restructuring of the administrative state. First, what are the most effective structures, taking into account both benefits and costs, of the intelligence bureaucracy and congressional oversight for national security? Second, what structures are politically and legally feasible? It is very difficult, though not impossible, to change jurisdictions of agencies and congressional committees. The Intelligence Reform and Terrorism Prevention Act of 2004 made potentially significant changes to the intelligence community but did not touch congressional boundaries. Third, what structures should a democratic society desire? How does the organization of the intelligence community and congressional oversight affect core liberal democratic values? This paper questions the siren call of unification, in terms of national security effectiveness, political feasibility, and democratic legitimacy, and suggests future avenues for research.


 
Degan on Taxing Commuting Expenses Tsilly Dagan (Bar-Ilan University, Faculty of Law) has posted Ordinary People Necessary Choices on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    This Article reexamines some fundamental tax policy concepts through the analysis of commuting expenses. It challenges the well-entrenched distinction between personal and business expenses. This distinction, I argue, conceals fundamental normative choices that should be openly discussed. Indeed, this Article suggests that resorting to the substantive grounds for the allowance of certain expenses explicitly is normatively superior to using the seemingly technical personal-business distinction. Furthermore, such a strategy provides a more workable doctrinal framework. In its search for appropriate substantive foundations, the Article draws not only on the conventional considerations of efficiency and distributive justice, but also on considerations that are novel to tax policy - identity and community. This Article uses commuting expenses as a case study. A critical examination of tax law's disallowance of commuting expenses demonstrates the futility of the business-personal distinction. In its stead, the Article analyzes the economic efficiency of allowing a deduction for commuting expenses; it uses the vast empirical literature on commuting to demonstrate the significant distributive questions involved; and it highlights the importance of community and identity considerations to the discourse of deductions in general and of commuting expenses in particular. Finally, this Article suggests a mechanism that would properly address the distributive and efficiency concerns while fully tackling identity and community issues.


Sunday, January 29, 2006
 
Legal Theory Calendar The Calendar is still in progress.
    Monday, January 30
      Rutgers-Camden Law: Larence Solum, The Supreme Court in Bondage: Constitutional Stare Decisis, Legal Formalism, and the Future of Unenumerated Rights. See you there!
      UCLA Law: Professor Bill Henderson Indiana University School of Law-Bloomington, "An Empirical Study of Single-Tier versus Two-Tier Partnerships in the AM Law 200"
      Hofstra Law: Seth Harris, New York Law School, “Law, Economics, and Accommodations in the Internal Labor Market”
      NYU Law: Richard Primus.
    Tuesday, January 31
      Marquette Law: Eric Goldman, Marquette University Law School, Placing and Marketing Scholarship
    Wednesday, February 1
      University of London, Institute of Education: Patricia White (IOE), Political Forgiveness and Civic Education.
      NYU Legal History: Claire Priest, Northwestern, “Creating an American Property Law: Alienability and its Limits in American History”
      Ohio State Law: Omri Ben-Shahar, Contracts Without Consent
      UCLA Legal History: Dennis J. Ventry, Jr., UCLA, "Family Tax Inequities and Community Property Law, 1913-1930"
    Thursday, February 2
      Oxford Jurisprudence Discussion Group: Kevin Toh, Raz on Detachment and Describability
      Stanford Law & Economics: Daniel Kelly (U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit), "The 'Public Use' Requirement in Eminent Domain Law: A Rationale Based on Secret Purchases and Private Influence"
      Lewis & Clark Law: Anita Bernstein, Emory, Keep It Simple: An Explanation of the Rule of No Recovery for Pure Economic Loss
      Boston University Law: Mike Meurer and Maureen O'Rourke, Contract and Coordination Failure: Mandatory and Prohibited Terms in Intellectual Property Licenses.
      Brooklyn Law: Wendy Seltzer, Brooklyn Law School, The Chilling Effects of Legal Threats to Online Speech—and Ways to Warm the Air.
      Florida State Law: Suzanna Sherry, Vanderbilt University Law School.
      Fordham Law: Thomas H. Lee, Fordham & Visiting Columbia, "The World Balance of Power and the Evolution of U.S. Foreign Relations Law"
      UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Lawrence Sager, Texas.
      NYU Colloquium on Tax Policy & Public Finance: Jason Furman, NYU Wagner School, “Coping With Demographic Uncertainty.”
      Northwestern Law, Advanced Topics in Taxation: Steven A. Bank, Professor of Law, University of California at Los Angeles, "Dividends and Tax Policy in the Long-Run"
      Oxford Comparative Law Discussion Group: Dr Péter Gárdos, Fundamental Conceptions of the Basis of Civil Liability: Insights from the Draft Hungarian Civil Code
    Friday, February 3
      University of Georgia Law: Jim Rossi (Florida State): Approaching Deference for State Regulators in Antitrust Law Through Chevron.
      Notre Dame Law: Ernest A. Young, Texas.
      Georgetown Law & Economics: Jonathan Klick, Florida State University College of Law, "Incomplete Contracts and Opportunism in Franchising Arrangements: The Role of Termination Clauses"
      Boston College Law: Michelle J. Anderson, Professor of Law, Villanova University School of Law.
      University of Illinois Law: East Asia Undisciplined: Law, Economics, and Institutions in East Asia
        12:30 Ethan Michelson, University of Indiana, Guanxi in the Chinese Legal System 12:55 Jacques deLisle, Law, University of Pennsylvania, TBA 1:30 Jonathan Marshall, Political Science, Carthage College, Institutional Barriers, Cause Lawyers, and Citizen Litigation in Japan 2:00 Kentaro Koga, Illinois, Bank Relations and Security Analyst Forecasts among Japanese Firms 2:30 Glenn Hoetker, Illinois, Supplier Relationships in the Japanese Economy
    University of Florida, Conference: DATA DEVOLUTION: Corporate Information Security, Consumers and the Future of Regulation.


 
Legal Theory Lexicon: Balancing Tests
    Introduction Balancing tests are ubiquitous in American law. From the Due Process Clause to the Freedom of Speech and from the federal joinder rules to personal jurisdiction, U.S. law makes the outcome of legal disputes dependant on the balancing of various interests and factors. Law students quickly become familiar with the idea of a balancing test, and moreover, are likely to quickly develop a cynical attitude about their constraining power. "So it's just subjective?"--is a question often asked in classroom discussion when a balancing test is announced. This post provides a rough and ready introduction to the theoretical issues raised by the notion of a "balancing test." As always, my intended audience consists of law students, especially first years, with an interest in legal theory.
    Case-by-Case versus Systemic Balancing The first distinction to master when thinking about balancing tests is that between case-by-case and systemic balancing. When a court adopts a case=by-case balancing test, the test is applied to each case, one case at a time. For example, in personal jurisdiction law, a case-by-case balancing test is used to determine whether assertions of personal jurisdiction are consistent with the Due Process Clause. But not all balancing is done on a case-by-case basis. For example, Mathews v. Eldridge announced a balancing test for determining whether pre-deprivation hearings are required by Due Process. This balancing test is applied to general categories (types) of deprivations. Once it has been determine that the balancing test does not require a hearing in category (e.g. Social Security disability benefit cases), the result is a categorical rule that can be applied to the category without further balancing.
    There is, of course, an analogy between the difference between case-by-case versus systemic balancing and the difference between act and rule utilitarianism. Act utilitarianism makes the rightness of an action depend on the consequences of that individual action. Rule utilitarianism makes the rightness of an action depend on whether the action conforms to the system of rules that would produce the best consequences. This analogy points to a larger concept--the scope of decision problem. Many legal theories assume that the scope of decision is an individual action or case, whereas others look to individual legal rules and yet others look to types of rules.
    Here is a nifty move, made famous by David Lyons (the legal philosopher who teaches at Boston University). Lyons argued that rule utilitarianism could be shown to be extensionally equivalent to act utilitarianism. His argument was beautifully simple. Take a rule and a particular action that would be required by act utilitarianism but forbidden by the utility maximizing rule. Now imagine an exception to the rule that would allow the utility maximizing action to be treated differently. The new rule-plus-exception produces more utility than the old rule. Hence rule utilitarianism requires the new rule. Lyons argued that we can iterate this move until rule utilitarianism and act utilitarianism require exactly the same results.
    One more point about case-by-case versus systemic balancing. Both kinds of balancing can be done ex post (backwards looking) or ex ante fowards looking. Take the Learned Hand balancing test for negligence. This test requires us to compare the cost of safety (ex post) against the benefits (ex post). This is ex post, case-by-case balancing. But when courts decide whether to issue an injunction, they sometimes "balance the equities," ex ante, asking whether the injuries done if the injunction does not issue will outweigh those that will result if the injunction is entered--in the future. Likewise, systemic balancing can be done either ex post or ex ante.
    What is Balanced? Yet another question that must be faced by any balancing test is "What is balanced?" Courts seem to think that just about any sort of interest or factor can be balanced. One kind of balancing test is represented by the International Shoe test for personal jurisdiction. This test balances interests--i.e. the interest of the plaintiff in the forum, the interest of the forum in the dispute, and so forth. Another kind of balancing test takes a varity of so-called factors into account: "prejudice to the defendant," "the impact on nonparties," and so forth in the case of tests for mandatory joinder. Properly speaking, such factors cannot really be balanced. Interests belong on the same scale--at least if they are the right kind of interests, but "factors" are usually considerations that bear in complex ways on a decision. The integration of multiple factors into a decision may involve balancing, but it also may involve reasoning that doesn’t actually weigh and compare commensurables.
    The Commensurability Problem This last point about balancing tests leads to a very fundamental idea in legal theory. Some approaches to moral theory make all ultimate values commensurable. In contemporary law and economics, for example, one approach reduces all value to preference-satisfaction, which then can be weighed via a Bergson-Samuelson social utility function. W(x) = F {U1(x), U2(x), . . UN(x)}, where F is some increasing function, U1 is the utility of state of affairs X for individual number 1, and so forth. Although some forms of consequentialism have the property of making all values commensurable, many moral theories do not have this property. Deontological ethics and virtue ethics, for example, generally are interpreted as maintaining that not all values are commensurable and hence as denying that balancing is even possible in some choice situations.
    The commensurability problem also provides a nifty move for legal theorists. If someone proposes a balancing test, ask yourself if the things that it requires to be weighed are such that they really can be measured on the same scale. If not, then the proposed balancing test simply will not be able to do the work assigned to it.
    Balancing Tests and the Rule of Law Yet another issue concerning balancing tests is the fancy version of the law student's intuition that balancing tests are subjective. Justice Scalia, for example, has argued that balancing tests undermine the rule of law because of their subjectivity and elasticity. If we believe that the rule of law values--certainty and predictability of the law--are very great social goods, then we have a general reason to prefer categorical rules to balancing tests. On the other hand, some balancing tests may be actually be more predictable than some rules with respect to a particular problem. For example, a case could be made that the "purposeful availment" component of the International Shoe test for personal jurisdiction is more subjective than the multifactor balancing component of the Shoe test. Some rules are very fuzzy; some balancing tests are quite precise.
    Conclusion Balancing tests are so common in American law, that you might begin to take them for granted, but that would be a mistake. Almost every balancing test raises interesting issues of legal theory. I hope this post has provided you with the tools to begin asking those questions.
For a collection of all the Legal Theory Lexicon posts, surf here.


Saturday, January 28, 2006
 
Legal Theory Bookworm The Legal Theory Bookworm recommends Educating Oneself in Public : Critical Essays in Jurisprudence by Michael S. Moore. Here's a blurb:
    The eleven essays in Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence constitute an education in the Anglo-American jurisprudence of the second half of the twentieth century. The book examines both the thought of major figures such as H. L. A. Hart, Joseph Raz, Ronald Dworkin, Lon Fuller, and Richard Rorty, and the general themes of major movements such as legal realism, post-modernism, and pragmatism. Despite this focus on the thoughts of others the book is not a survey but is a critical probing of particular ideas often attributed to such figures. Detailed depth of understanding is sought about: Hart's conception of a `general jurisprudence' that describes law in general; Dworkin's conception of an `internal jurisprudence' that interprets the concept of law of our legal culture; Fuller's ideal of a `functional jurisprudence' that seeks the essence of law in the values it serves; the place of rules in legal and moral reasoning; Raz's idea that laws give `exclusionary reasons' to legal actors subject to such laws; how judges should reason, according to the legal realists; whether there are right answers to all disputed law cases; whether behind the obvious law of legal rules there can exist an unobvious law of legal principles; Finnis's conception of the common good as the function law uniquely serves; in what sense law practice and legal theory are interpretive activities; whether all knowledge, or some discrete realm of knowledge, is peculiarly interpretive in character. Michael Moore's views on each of these topics are detailed and original, even if the springboards for each discussion are the writings of those who introduced such topics into modern discussions. The introductory chapter includes responses by many of the figures examined in the other essays, together with the author's rejoinders.
Moore is superb, and these essays address many of the central topics in contemporary philosophy of law. Highly recommended!


 
Download of the Week The Download of the Week is Law, Science, and Morality: A Review of Richard Posner's The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory by John Mikhail. Here is the abstract:
    In The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory, Judge Richard Posner argues that moral and legal theory are largely worthless in their own right and have little if anything to contribute to legal scholarship. In this review essay, I first summarize the major themes of Problematics and then evaluate Posner's arguments on their merits. Among the main points I make are the following. First, the most conspicuous feature of Problematics is Posner's failure to engage in any serious way with the model of moral theory described by Rawls in A Theory of Justice. In keeping with a traditional analogy, Rawls’ model is organized around a series of comparisons between rules of justice and rules of grammar. The model begins from the empirical assumption that each person develops a sense of justice under normal circumstances, an assumption it takes to be the best explanation of the moral analogue of what linguists and cognitive scientists call the projection problem. The model then identifies the first task of moral philosophy to be an accurate description of the sense of justice, thereby solving the moral analogue of what linguists and cognitive scientists call the problem of descriptive adequacy. The model follows the standard practice of the cognitive sciences in distinguishing a person’s operative moral principles (those principles actually operative in her exercise of moral judgment) from her express principles (those principles she verbalizes in an effort to explain or justify her judgments). Finally, the model draws a distinction between moral performance (a person's actual exercise of moral judgment in concrete situations) and moral competence (the mental capacity or cognitive system underlying those judgments) in a sense analogous to the linguistic competence-performance distinction first introduced by Chomsky in Aspects of the Theory of Syntax and now used throughout the cognitive sciences. Posner's failure to address these and other plausible features of Rawls' model vitiates much of what he says in Problematics about morality and moral theory. Second, Posner's defense of moral relativism is undermined by his mistaken assumption that alleged moral universals such as "murder is wrong" are nothing more than vacuous tautologies. This assumption is false: the proposition "murder is wrong" is not analytic, but synthetic - as Locke and Hume, among others, recognized, and as any well-developed criminal code will attest. Moreover, Posner's contention that the prohibition of murder is not universal is not only unfounded but contradicted by the very sources he cites in his book. Finally, Posner fails to come to terms in any serious way with the hypothesis that human beings share a sense of justice rich enough to support a system of universal human rights and obligations, including the right not to be murdered. This hypothesis is plausible and supported by a considerable body of empirical evidence. Throughout Problematics, Posner adopts the mantle of science and pokes fun at philosophers for being unscientific. But, in truth, it is his relativism, not their universalism, which seems out of touch with modern science.
Download it while its hot!


Friday, January 27, 2006
 
Friday Calendar
    Boston College Law: Steven L. Schwarcz, Stanley A. Star Professor of Law & Business, Duke University School of Law.
    Oxford Centre for Competition Law & Policy: Peter Willis & Taylor Wessing, The privilege against self-incrimination in competition investigations
    All Souls College, Oxford, Neill Lecture: The Honourable Michael Beloff QC, Paying the Judges - Who, Whom, How Much and Why?
    Vanderbilt Faculty Workshop: Don Herzog, University of Michigan Law School, "The Kerr Principle, State Action and Legal Rights"
    University of Syracus, Sawyer Law and Politics Program Research Workshop: Petra Hejnova, Maxwell School, "Women's Mobilization and Democratic Transitions: A Study of Regional Patterns"
    University of Georgia Law: Ronald Rotunda (George Mason), The Detainee Cases of 2004 and Their Aftermath
    Michigan State University: THIRD ANNUAL INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY & COMMUNICATIONS LAW AND POLICY SCHOLARS ROUNDTABLE


 
Rossi on Gardner on State Constitutions Jim Rossi (Florida State University College of Law) has posted The Puzzle of State Constitutions on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    In his new book, 'Interpreting State Constitutions: A Jurisprudence of Function in a Federal System' (University of Chicago Press 2005), James Gardner positions state constititions and their interpretation within federalism, in contrast to others who see state constitutions as largely independent of the federal constitution or as meriting primacy as their own interpretive texts. As Gardner suggests, understanding state constitutions within the larger national system challenges theorists to focus on the function that state constitutions, and sub-national constitutions more generally, perform within a national system. Gardner argues that a functional approach licenses courts to interpret state constitutions instrumentally to facilitate state resistance to national power. He endorses a rebuttable presumption that construes state judicial power to resist federal authority broadly, envisioning a bolder role than alternative theories for state courts in promoting federalism. After summarizing Gardner's approach, I will discuss two possible objections to it. First, his account is based on the primary goal of federalism as protecting liberty (broadly defined) against intrusion by national authorities. This liberty-based understanding of federalism, however, ignores or downplays that federalism may be understood in ways that are agnostic towards national authority. A broader understanding of federalism would give state courts clearer direction in implementing the goals of federalism and also would allow Gardner to extend his interpretive theory to subnational constitutional interpretation contexts outside of the U.S., where the protection of liberty may not have claim to being a primary historical rational for the recognition of state power. Second, even if we accept Gardner's account of federalism, his approach sees the core interpretive problem of state constitutionalism as centered around judicial power to resist the reach of national power. This court-centered approach downplays other important features of state constitutionalism. For example, as the recent disputes over same-sex marriage in California and Oregon remind us, other branches of government, such as the legislature or executive, could have a superior claim to interpreting a state constitution. Further, in some contexts there are strong reasons for understanding state constitutions as being focused on facilitating, not resisting, federal power. To the extent Gardner’s approach views courts as "resistors" rather than "facilitators" of national authority, his interpretive tools may be limited in their ability to serve the goals of state constitutions - as where a state branch other than a court resists federal power and courts support it. Gardner’s interpretive account does little to help courts solve such conflicts, thus inviting courts and scholars to do further interpretational groundwork. Notwithstanding these concerns, the broader framework Gardner lays out is the strongest starting place for a theory of state constitutional interpretation. His innovations for state constitutionalism allows scholars and courts to conceptualize a state constitution as something more than a positivist text in a jurisdictional vacuum, without rendering state constitutions irrelevant given the existence of national power in a federalist system. Gardner's functionalist approach and presumptions should be taken as a challenge for state courts, even though I believe that a mature enterprise of state constitutional interpretation must do more than adhere to a liberty-based notion of federalism or focus exclusively (or necessarily even primarily) on judicial interpretation.
I always find Rossi's work to be illuminating and the theory of state constitutionalism is an important and (in my opinion) undertheorized topic. Highly recommended.


 
Ryan on Breyer and Sunstein James E. Ryan (University of Virginia School of Law) has posted Does It Take a Theory? Originalism, Active Liberty and Minimalism (Stanford Law Review, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    This review essay examines two recent books, Active Liberty by Justice Stephen Breyer, and Radicals In Robes by Professor Cass Sunstein, and it assesses them in relation to their main target – Justice Scalia and his brand of originalism. Both books are self-consciously designed to influence public debate over how best to interpret the Constitution, a debate that originalists have dominated for the last fifteen years or so. There is much to admire in these books. Both are engaging and at times quite provocative. Justice Breyer’s book is candid and smart. He offers no pat answers or simplified formula for deciding cases, which is to his credit and speaks well of his intellectual honesty. Professor Sunstein’s book, in turn, is quite effective in poking holes in the form of originalism he dubs “fundamentalism” and in highlighting the numerous instances where “fundamentalists” like Justices Scalia and Thomas seem to deviate from their avowed methodology. For those who have been waiting for a public response from the left, these books are a sight for sore eyes, if for no other reason than they constitute an attempt to push back at the level of ideas. And yet the books fall a bit flat, at least in the eyes of this (sympathetic) reader. The basic problem is suggested by the title of this review: neither Justice Breyer nor Professor Sunstein offers and justifies a theory of constitutional interpretation. Justice Breyer comes closer than Professor Sunstein. But in my view, neither Active Liberty nor Radicals in Robes explains and justifies, in terms plain enough to influence public debate, how judges ought to decide cases. In their haste to distance themselves from originalism, moreover, both Justice Breyer and Sunstein seem to distance themselves from the text of the constitution. These seem to me fatal missteps in their effort to persuade a general audience to reject originalism and embrace an alternative. In addition, both books only partially succeed in their critique of originalism. Breyer and Sunstein focus on one form of originalism, which entails looking to the narrowly conceived expectations of the framers. While this may indeed be the way originalism is occasionally practiced by Scalia and others, it is not the only version of originalism conceivable. Nor is it necessarily the one most faithful to the text of the Constitution, which, at the end of the day, is the point of originalism. What is ironic about both books is that each contains seeds of an alternative, originalist-oriented approach. But neither Breyer nor Sunstein explores whether that alternative might be superior both to the originalism they criticize and the approaches they advocate. Indeed, absent a compelling alternative theory, one wonders if Breyer and Sunstein should have sought to mend rather than end originalism.
And here is a bit more from the text itself:
    [T]here can be a difference between meaning and expectations. The founding generations may have expected particular results to follow from constitutional language. But these expectations may or may not be consistent with the actual and proper meaning of the text. They might be the result of misinterpretations of language or time-bound prejudices and beliefs that obscure the proper application of the text. Moreover, it seems likely that, given the language they used in many provisions, the founding generation recognized that some constitutional provisions established general principles that would not themselves change, but might have different applications in different contexts.36 Put differently, the founders would have recognized, as we should, that their specific expectations did not settle the meaning of the text.
And a bit more from later in the review:
    If [originalisms tendency to produce bad policies] is indeed one of [Sunstein and Breyer's] arguments against originalism, it is both overblown and potentially self-defeating. It is overblown insofar as it ignores the role of stare decisis. Sunstein is guiltier on this score, as his parade of horribles assumes that originalist judges are willing to overturn precedent in order to achieve their more perfect vision of the Constitution. Yet as he acknowledges, most judges, as well as Justice Scalia, believe in stare decisis.86 So it is hard to agree that the sky would necessarily fall if the Supreme Court became more originalist in orientation while at the same time maintaining a healthy respect for stare decisis. What is more, it is hard to see how Sunstein’s own approach -- or any single coherent approach to the Constitution, for that matter -- would necessarily lead to all or even most of the results that Sunstein now wants to preserve. It seems unfair to imagine originalism without stare decisis and catalogue the awful results, without engaging in a similar thought experiment where minimalism is the approach and there are no precedents to preserve or build from.
Highly recommended! Download it while its hot!


 
Greeen on Employment Discrimination Mediation Michael Z. Green (Texas Wesleyan University) has posted Tackling Employment Discrimination With ADR: Does Mediation Offer A Shield for the Haves or Real Opportunity for the Have-Nots? (Berkeley Journal of Employment and Labor Law, Forthcoming) on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    This paper explores the benefits of using mediation in addressing employment discrimination disputes. It highlights the difficulties for those who expect too much out of mediation by expecting it to transform relations while exposing concerns with those who limit mediation's potential by supporting mythical notions about mediators being neutral. The paper suggests that employers develop comprehensive conflict resolution systems and include mediation as a process that is case-specific and focused on the needs of all parties and not the needs of the mediator.


 
White on Jackson's Youngstown Opinion Adam White has posted Justice Jackson’s Draft Opinions In The Steel Seizure Cases on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    Justice Robert H. Jackson's opinion in Youngstown Sheet & Tube - also known as The Steel Seizure Cases - is, of course, no ordinary lone concurrence. As the nation debates executive action in the Global War on Terror, that opinion has grown ubiquitous in legal discourse. Jackson's analysis - including the famous tripartite framework for the evaluation of Executive action - now borders on conventional wisdom. Nonetheless, as Jackson's draft opinions reveal, that analysis did not spring fully-formed from the Justice's mind. Rather, it was the product of his deliberation, draft, and re-draft. His papers reveal not only the substantive evolution of his views, but also his changing efforts to justify the wartime actions of FDR as well as his own participation in the case. His drafts reflect his own ambivalence toward judicial limitation on the powers of the President, particularly in his reference to Korematsu, as well as his deep concern - relatively muted in his final opinion - that Congress would be unwilling to check the President. In sum, they warn of the folly inherent in reducing Jackson's views to a bullet-point version of his tripartite framework. Jackson's views - like the institutions he analyzed - are not so simple.
I've always been fascinated by Jackson's concurrence--one of the most important foundations of contemporary separation of powers doctrine, but (in my opinion) a horribly wrong turn. White's piece sheds light on Jackson's own ambivalence about this case.


 
Kaplan on Tax Policy and Family Care for Older Adults Richard Kaplan (Illinois) has posted Federal Tax Policy and Family-Provided Care for Older Adults (Virginia Tax Review (vol. 25, no. 2), Fall 2005 issue, pp. 509-562) on SSRN. Here's the abstract:
    An issue of enormous and increasing significance to the vast majority of older Americans, and their families, is who will care for them as they age and require assistance in their daily lives. Such assistance is usually denominated "long-term care," because it is a chronic phenomenon that is not limited to some specific medical incident. Such care can be provided in a variety of settings, depending upon the intensity of the older person's needs and the medical nature of those needs, but 80% of long-term care is provided by family members and close friends on an informal and typically unpaid basis. This phenomenon reflects a wide range of cultural norms in this country, as well as certain economic realities. As more Americans attain ages at which some assistance with daily life activities is typical, the federal tax treatment of family-provided elder care will become increasingly important. This Article considers how the provision of informal care for older family members is taxed presently and how such treatment should be changed in light of changing family dynamics. It begins with a brief description of what informal elder care consists of and the impact of such care responsibilities on the family members who provide that care. The Article then considers how courts have assessed informal caregiving in the context of gratuitous transfers by the recipients of such care. It then examines the tax treatment of informal caregiving as it relates to the personal exemption and the deduction of medical expenses. The Article next analyzes a number of recent legislative proposals that would provide tax credits for family caregivers. The Article concludes with some policy responses to this growing societal concern.


Thursday, January 26, 2006
 
Thursday Calendar
    Oxford Jurisprudence Discussion Group: Alan Norrie, War crime and the failure of law: Arendt, Jaspers and the ontology of guilt
    Boston University Law: David Walker, Financial Accounting, Corporate Behavior, and the Promise of Offensive Accounting
    Brooklyn Law: Margaret A. Berger, Brooklyn Law School, Vioxx: A Roadmap of Fissures in Our Legal and Healthcare Systems
    Florida State Law: Charlene Luke, Florida State University School of Law
    UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Charles Beitz, Professor of Politics, Princeton University
    Kings College, London: Angus Dawson (Keele) Children's vaccinations, best interests and parental disagreement.
    Forum for European Philosophy, Institut Français, London: Rupert Read (UEA), Rawls and Habermas: Liberalism is inherently inegalitarian and unsustainable.
    Oxford EC Law Discussion Group & Oxford Comparative Law Discussion Group: Vanessa Mak, Harmonisation of European Contract Law: Problem Areas in the Sale of Goods Law
    UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: Annelise Riles.
    UCLA Tax Policy and Public FInance Workshop: Michael Livingston, Rutgers School of Law - Camden, Rendering Unto Caesar: Religious Perspectives on Progressive and Flat Taxation
    University College London, Current Legal Problems Lecture: Mr Gavin Phillipson (King's College London), "Deference, Discretion and Democracy: Judicial Reasoning under the Human Rights Act"
    University of Michigan, Law & Economics: Richard Nelson, Columbia, The Market Economy, and the Scientific Commons
    University of Texas Colloquium on Constitutional and Legal Theory: Jane Schacter (Wisconsin, Stanford), "Political Accountability, Proxy Accountability, and Democratic Legitimacy" & "Democracy Diminished"
    Yale Law Economics & Organizations: Professor James Poterba, MIT, Economics, Defined Contribution Plans and Retirement Saving Risk and also here.


Wednesday, January 25, 2006
 
Wednesday Calendar
    University College London, Colloquium in Legal and Social Philosophy: Janet Radcliffe Richards (University College, London) Equality of opportunity
    University College London, International Law Society: Professor Christine Chinkin, LSE, "Gender and international peace and security"
    Philosophy of Education, London: John Marshall, Multiculturalism and Culturual Plurality Revisited.
    NYU Law & History: Barry Friedman, Jacob D. Fuchsberg Professor of Law, NYU School of Law, "Neither Force Nor Will: The Popular Foundations of Judicial Review"
    Oxford, The Ethox Centre and Oxford Genetics Knowledge Park Seminar Series 2006: Professor Bartha Maria Knoppers, "The Public Population Project in Genomics (P3G) International Consortium for Linking Population Genomic Studies: What it is and what it offers."
    Oxford Criminology Seminar Series 2005/06: Julian Roberts, The Virtual Prison: Community Custody and the Evolution of Imprisonment
    Oxford Law Faculty: Jeremy Horder, A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (Consultation Paper no.177)
    University of Toronto: Lisa Philipps, York University, Partners in Business, Partners in Love: Tax Law and the Two-Person Career
    Villanova Law: David Wilkins, Harvard Law School.


 
Mikhail on Posner John Mikhail (Georgetown) has posted Law, Science, and Morality: A Review of Richard Posner's The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    In The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory, Judge Richard Posner argues that moral and legal theory are largely worthless in their own right and have little if anything to contribute to legal scholarship. In this review essay, I first summarize the major themes of Problematics and then evaluate Posner's arguments on their merits. Among the main points I make are the following. First, the most conspicuous feature of Problematics is Posner's failure to engage in any serious way with the model of moral theory described by Rawls in A Theory of Justice. In keeping with a traditional analogy, Rawls’ model is organized around a series of comparisons between rules of justice and rules of grammar. The model begins from the empirical assumption that each person develops a sense of justice under normal circumstances, an assumption it takes to be the best explanation of the moral analogue of what linguists and cognitive scientists call the projection problem. The model then identifies the first task of moral philosophy to be an accurate description of the sense of justice, thereby solving the moral analogue of what linguists and cognitive scientists call the problem of descriptive adequacy. The model follows the standard practice of the cognitive sciences in distinguishing a person’s operative moral principles (those principles actually operative in her exercise of moral judgment) from her express principles (those principles she verbalizes in an effort to explain or justify her judgments). Finally, the model draws a distinction between moral performance (a person's actual exercise of moral judgment in concrete situations) and moral competence (the mental capacity or cognitive system underlying those judgments) in a sense analogous to the linguistic competence-performance distinction first introduced by Chomsky in Aspects of the Theory of Syntax and now used throughout the cognitive sciences. Posner's failure to address these and other plausible features of Rawls' model vitiates much of what he says in Problematics about morality and moral theory. Second, Posner's defense of moral relativism is undermined by his mistaken assumption that alleged moral universals such as "murder is wrong" are nothing more than vacuous tautologies. This assumption is false: the proposition "murder is wrong" is not analytic, but synthetic - as Locke and Hume, among others, recognized, and as any well-developed criminal code will attest. Moreover, Posner's contention that the prohibition of murder is not universal is not only unfounded but contradicted by the very sources he cites in his book. Finally, Posner fails to come to terms in any serious way with the hypothesis that human beings share a sense of justice rich enough to support a system of universal human rights and obligations, including the right not to be murdered. This hypothesis is plausible and supported by a considerable body of empirical evidence. Throughout Problematics, Posner adopts the mantle of science and pokes fun at philosophers for being unscientific. But, in truth, it is his relativism, not their universalism, which seems out of touch with modern science.
Highly recommended!


 
Frost on Judicial Recusal Amanda Frost (American University) has posted Keeping Up Appearances on SSRN. Here is the abstract:
    The laws governing judicial recusal are failing to protect the reputation of the judiciary, as was illustrated by the recent controversy surrounding Justice Scalia's refusal to recuse himself from Cheney v. United States District Court for the District of Columbia. The history of recusal law reveals that each time Congress amends the recusal statutes to expand their scope, judges interpret the legal standards narrowly to avoid disqualification. This article contends that the recusal statutes are ineffective not because the substantive standards for recusal are too limited, but rather because the recusal process operates outside of the traditional adjudicatory model. For example, the very judge whose impartiality is being questioned is expected to raise and decide the question whether his or her own conduct creates the appearance of impartiality, and often makes that decision without issuing any explanation for it. Drawing on the literature locating the judiciary's legitimacy in traditional forms of adjudication, this article suggests that recusal law will only serve its purpose of protecting the judiciary's reputation if it incorporates these core procedural tenets of adjudication into the recusal decision. Specifically, the article proposes procedural reforms such as encouraging an adversarial presentation of the recusal question to an impartial judge who must issue a reasoned decision that will provide guidance for judges in future cases.
This is an important, underwritten, and undertheorized issue. Frost's article is a fine and welcome contribution!


 
More on Open Access Publishing & e-prints Michael Froomkin writes about his Copyright Experiences Wiki--a site that provides information about copyright policies of various legal publishers. It's a Wiki--so you (or we) can share information about various journals. Here's the description from the site:
    Welcome to the Copyright Experiences Wiki The purpose of this website is for legal academics and others to share our copyright experiences with law journals and other legal publishers. As academics, we have an interest in ensuring the widest dissemination of our work. Law Journals tend, however, to use standard-form copyright agreements that reqire a copyright assignment, and impose unreasonable restrictions on our rights to share and re-use our own work. Some law journals, however, are more enlightened. Others, when pushed, will also see the light. Due to the transitory nature of student-run law journal staffs, still others are actually unaware of their own past practices. This site will allow you to learn what other people have been able to persuade law journals to accept. On the pages linked from here, legal writers describe their copyright experiences. The information is as good or bad as what you contribute to it.
And John Oberdiek writes:
    Solove's PDF reprint idea. It turns out that Philosophy & Public Affairs is already doing this -- I believe they just switched over. Indeed, [a colleague] sent me the PDF reprint -- all that PAPA would provide -- of his article in the new issue. ...So maybe philosophers don't have to wait for the Owl of Minerva to take to the sky after all....


Tuesday, January 24, 2006
 
Are Reprints Obsolete?--with an Update Dan Solove has a very interesting post over at Concurring Opinions. Here's a taste:
    So here's my idea. I'm thinking of moving toward a system of electronic reprints. I could send out a PDF version of the final article in an email to everybody in my database. In other words, I'd shift from being a junk mailer to a spammer. . . . In my email, I'd include the text of the letter I would have sent to accompany the reprint, attach the article in PDF format, and possibly include a link to the final version of the paper on SSRN. I'd still order some reprints -- about 50 to 100 -- and offer to send hard copies of the reprints to anybody who requested them. My guess is that I'd get a few people requesting the actual reprint, but most people interested in reading the article would just print it out from the attached digital version.
Solove's post asks whether we would prefer digital reprints. For a long time, my answer would have been no. Why? Because paper is still easier to read. But now, I've switched positions on this. Digital reprints are much better--not because they are more readable (although that's improved a lot with Acrobat's amazing quality), but because they are easy to store and retrieve. Old reprints are very difficult to find. And let's face it, at some point they are lost or tossed. But digital reprints can be organzised, searched, and kept forever. Where do I sign up?
Update: Michael Froomkin comments on Solove's post:
    I think long attachments in bulk mailings are Not Nice. It can have nasty effect on recipient email systems if they get several. And if everyone starts doing it.... No, if you're going to go digital, include a link to an online copy, not an attachment.
Right! There are two solutions:
    1. Two tiers of e-print recipients: (i) secondary interest recipients (everyone in the field), who should get links, and (ii) primary interest recipients (those you cite or discuss or who are working on the topic), who can get the attachment.
    2. With respect to those who you email links, there is the problem of public access. Of course, if you publish in a journal that allows or provides a public access (free, downloadable) electronic version, this is not a problem. But some peer-reviewed journals charge a truly prohibitory fee for one-time downloads by nonsubscribers, i.e. $30 for one copy of one article. The best solution is do not publish in these journals.
I've moved this post to the top of the blog.


 
Book Announcement: Happy Lives & the HIghest Good by Lear
    Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Gabriel Richardson Lear To read the entire book description or the introduciton, please visit: http://pup.princeton.edu/titles/7751.html Gabriel Richardson Lear presents a bold new approach to one of the enduring debates about Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: the controversy about whether it coherently argues that the best life for humans is one devoted to a single activity, namely philosophical contemplation. "A fine book. Anyone interested in Aristotle's ethics should read it."--Norman O. Dahl, Philosophy in Review Paper | $19.95 / £12.95 | ISBN: 0-691-12626-7 Cloth | 2004 | $37.95 / £24.95 | ISBN: 0-691-11466-8


 
Tuesday Calendar


Monday, January 23, 2006
 
Monday Calendar
    Columbia Law & Economics: Omri Ben-Shahar, BOILERPLATE AND ECONOMIC POWER IN AUTO MANUFACTURING CONTRACTS (with James J. White)
    Florida State Law: Douglas Baird, University of Chicago Law School
    London School of Economics, Centre for Philosophy of the Natural and Social Sciences: Raimo Tuomela (Helsinki), Cooperation and the We-Perspective
    University of Texas Law: Abe Wickelgren (UT Economics) "Why Divorce Laws Matter: Incentives for Non-Contractible Marital Investments Under Unilateral and Consent Divorce
    Vanderbilit Law & Politics Seminar: Virginia Hettinger, University of Connecticut Political Science, & Wendy Martinek, SUNY Binghamton Political Science, "Judging on a Collegial Court: Influences on Federal Appellate Decision Making"


 
Welcome to the Blogosphere . . . . . . to Feminist Law Professors, with Ann Bartow and Wendy Gordon, Caitlin Borgmann, Jenny Rivera, Rebecca M. Bratspies, Ruthann Robson, Katherine Franke, Susan Sturm, Martha Fineman, Sonia Katyal, Rebecca Tushnet, Amy Adler, Sylvia Law, Kimberly Yuracko, Margaret Chon, Deborah Rhode, Ellen Podgor, JoAnne Epps, Kathryn Stanchi, Madhavi Sunder, Berta Hernandez, Nancy Dowd, Elizabeth B. Brandt, Maureen Laflin, Anita L. Allen-Castellitto, Regina Austin, Fran Ansley, Jennifer Hendricks, Joan MacLeod Heminway, Mae Quinn, Llewellyn Gibbons, and Jessica Litman. That's quite a line up!


 
Symposium Announcement: The Future of Unenumerated Rights
    THE FUTURE OF UNENUMERATED RIGHTS Friday, February 10, 2006 9:15-5:30 Levy Conference Center University of Pennsylvania Law School 3400 Chestnut Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104 Keynote Speaker
      Louis H. Pollak, Senior Judge, United States District Court for the Eastern District of Pennsylvania
    Symposium Participants
      Gregory S. Alexander, Cornell Law School Randy Barnett, Boston University School of Law Rebecca L. Brown, Vanderbilt University Law School Jesse Choper, University of California, Berkeley (Boalt Hall) James W. Ely, Jr., Vanderbilt University Law School Stephen M. Feldman, University of Wyoming College of Law Howard Gillman, University of Southern California Department of Political Science Frank Goodman, University of Pennsylvania Law School Mark A. Graber, University of Maryland, College Park, and University of Maryland School of Law R.H. Helmholz, University of Chicago Law School Ken I. Kersch, Princeton University Department of Politics Seth Kreimer, University of Pennsylvania Law School Frank Michelman, Harvard Law School Kermit Roosevelt, University of Pennsylvania Law School Theodore Ruger, University of Pennsylvania Law School Jane Schacter, University of Wisconsin Law School Lawrence B. Solum, University of Illinois College of Law Mark Tushnet, Georgetown University Law Center Robin West, Georgetown University Law Center
    For a symposium schedule and speaker bios click here. For more information please contact Tony Falcone.


Sunday, January 22, 2006
 
Legal Theory Calendar
    Monday, January 23
      Columbia Law & Economics: Omri Ben-Shahar, BOILERPLATE AND ECONOMIC POWER IN AUTO MANUFACTURING CONTRACTS (with James J. White)
      Florida State Law: Douglas Baird, University of Chicago Law School
      London School of Economics, Centre for Philosophy of the Natural and Social Sciences: Raimo Tuomela (Helsinki), Cooperation and the We-Perspective
      University of Texas Law: Abe Wickelgren (UT Economics) "Why Divorce Laws Matter: Incentives for Non-Contractible Marital Investments Under Unilateral and Consent Divorce
      Vanderbilit Law & Politics Seminar: Virginia Hettinger, University of Connecticut Political Science, & Wendy Martinek, SUNY Binghamton Political Science, "Judging on a Collegial Court: Influences on Federal Appellate Decision Making"
    Tuesday, January 24 Wednesday, January 25
      University College London, Colloquium in Legal and Social Philosophy: Janet Radcliffe Richards (University College, London) Equality of opportunity
      University College London, International Law Society: Professor Christine Chinkin, LSE, "Gender and international peace and security"
      Philosophy of Education, London: John Marshall, Multiculturalism and Culturual Plurality Revisited.
      NYU Law & History: Barry Friedman, Jacob D. Fuchsberg Professor of Law, NYU School of Law, "Neither Force Nor Will: The Popular Foundations of Judicial Review"
      Oxford, The Ethox Centre and Oxford Genetics Knowledge Park Seminar Series 2006: Professor Bartha Maria Knoppers, "The Public Population Project in Genomics (P3G) International Consortium for Linking Population Genomic Studies: What it is and what it offers."
      Oxford Criminology Seminar Series 2005/06: Julian Roberts, The Virtual Prison: Community Custody and the Evolution of Imprisonment
      Oxford Law Faculty: Jeremy Horder, A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (Consultation Paper no.177)
      University of Toronto: Lisa Philipps, York University, Partners in Business, Partners in Love: Tax Law and the Two-Person Career
      Villanova Law: David Wilkins, Harvard Law School.
    Thursday, January 26
      Oxford Jurisprudence Discussion Group: Alan Norrie, War crime and the failure of law: Arendt, Jaspers and the ontology of guilt
      Boston University Law: David Walker, Financial Accounting, Corporate Behavior, and the Promise of Offensive Accounting
      Brooklyn Law: Margaret A. Berger, Brooklyn Law School, Vioxx: A Roadmap of Fissures in Our Legal and Healthcare Systems
      Florida State Law: Charlene Luke, Florida State University School of Law
      UC Berkeley, Kadish Center: Charles Beitz, Professor of Politics, Princeton University
      Kings College, London: Angus Dawson (Keele) Children's vaccinations, best interests and parental disagreement.
      Forum for European Philosophy, Institut Français, London: Rupert Read (UEA), Rawls and Habermas: Liberalism is inherently inegalitarian and unsustainable.
      Oxford EC Law Discussion Group & Oxford Comparative Law Discussion Group: Vanessa Mak, Harmonisation of European Contract Law: Problem Areas in the Sale of Goods Law
      UCLA Legal Theory Workshop: Annelise Riles.
      UCLA Tax Policy and Public FInance Workshop: Michael Livingston, Rutgers School of Law - Camden, Rendering Unto Caesar: Religious Perspectives on Progressive and Flat Taxation
      University College London, Current Legal Problems Lecture: Mr Gavin Phillipson (King's College London), "Deference, Discretion and Democracy: Judicial Reasoning under the Human Rights Act"
      University of Michigan, Law & Economics: Richard Nelson, Columbia, The Market Economy, and the Scientific Commons
      University of Texas Colloquium on Constitutional and Legal Theory: Jane Schacter (Wisconsin, Stanford), "Political Accountability, Proxy Accountability, and Democratic Legitimacy" & "Democracy Diminished"
      Yale Law Economics & Organizations: Professor James Poterba, MIT, Economics, Defined Contribution Plans and Retirement Saving Risk and also here.
    Friday, January 27
      Boston College Law: Steven L. Schwarcz, Stanley A. Star Professor of Law & Business, Duke University School of Law.
      Oxford Centre for Competition Law & Policy: Peter Willis & Taylor Wessing, The privilege against self-incrimination in competition investigations
      All Souls College, Oxford, Neill Lecture: The Honourable Michael Beloff QC, Paying the Judges - Who, Whom, How Much and Why?
      Vanderbilt Faculty Workshop: Don Herzog, University of Michigan Law School, "The Kerr Principle, State Action and Legal Rights"
      University of Syracus, Sawyer Law and Politics Program Research Workshop: Petra Hejnova, Maxwell School, "Women's Mobilization and Democratic Transitions: A Study of Regional Patterns"
      University of Georgia Law: Ronald Rotunda (George Mason), The Detainee Cases of 2004 and Their Aftermath
      Michigan State University: THIRD ANNUAL INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY & COMMUNICATIONS LAW AND POLICY SCHOLARS ROUNDTABLE
    Saturday, January 28
      Michigan State University: THIRD ANNUAL INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY & COMMUNICATIONS LAW AND POLICY SCHOLARS ROUNDTABLE (continues)


 
Legal Theory Lexicon: Procedural Justice
    Introduction Recently, the Legal Theory Lexicon provided a very general entry on the the topic of justice. The notion of justice can be analyzed in many ways, but one good place to start is with Aristotle. Aristotle divides the topic of justice into two main parts, corrective justice and distributive justice. Distributive justice concerns the division of shares in social benefits and burdens; thus, many questions of tax policy are questions of distributive justice. Corrective justice involves the rectification of injustice, and thus includes a variety of topics from criminal law, torts, and contracts, among many others. Supplementing Aristotle's account, let us say that "procedural justice" is concerned with the means by which social groups (including governments, private institutions, and families) institutionalize the application of requirements of corrective and distributive justice to particular cases. This entry in the Lexicon provides an introduction to the idea of procedural justice for law students (especially first years) with an interest in legal theory.
    Slicing a Cake Our approach to the idea of procedural justice may be made easier by using a simple example. Consider the familiar procedure for dividing a cake: the person who slices the cake picks last. What makes this a fair procedure? One answer to this question might be the following: there is an independent criterion of what constitutes a fair outcome, equal slices for all, and the slicer-picks-last rule assures that we will get to this outcome. Slicer-picks-last is fair because guarantees accuracy. Or does it? If we really wanted to assure perfectly equal slices, then we could use a compass and the principles of plane geometry, with equal shares as a more reliable result. But this strikes us as an undue amount of fuss to go through when slicing a cake. Perhaps, the reason we believe that the slicer-picks-last rule is a fair procedure is that it strikes a fair balance between the importance of the outcome and the cost of getting there: the rule gets us close to equal shares most of the time at a reasonable price. Slicer-picks last might be considered fair, because does a good job of balancing. Or is there something more to the idea that the slicer-picks-last rule is fair? Maybe the reason we believe that the slicer gets a fair share is because the slicer was the one who did the cutting; the slicer's participation in the cutting validates the outcome, even if the slicer ends up with a smaller slice (or among the calorie conscious, a bigger slice). Slicer-picks-last could be a fair rule, because of process independently of outcome.
    Perfect, Imperfect, and Pure Procedural Justice These questions about the fairness of procedures for slicing a cake can be generalized by setting out a framework for analyzing the idea of procedural justice. In A Theory of Justice, John Rawls distinguishes three very general and abstract kinds of procedural justice: (1) perfect procedural justice, (2) imperfect procedural justice, and (3) pure procedural justice. Consider perfect procedural justice first. There are, he writes,
      two characteristic features of perfect procedural justice. First, there is an independent criterion of what is a fair division, a criterion defined separately from and prior to the procedure which is to be followed. And second, it is possible to devise a procedure that is sure to give that desired outcome.
    Rawls argues that our rule for the slicing of cakes is an example of perfect procedural justice. The person who slices picks last; Rawls believes that this procedure insures the equal division of shares. "Equal shares for each" is the independent criterion of a fair division; the slicer-picks-last rule is the procedure that reliably produces that outcome.
    In the case of imperfect procedural justice, the first characteristic, an independent criterion for fairness of outcome, is present, but the second, a procedure that guarantees that outcome, is not. Rawls contends:
      Imperfect procedural justice is exemplified by a criminal trial. The desired outcome is that the defendant should be declared guilty if and only if he has committed the offense with which he is charged. The trial procedure is framed to search for and to establish the truth in this regard. But it seems impossible to design the legal rules so that they always lead to the correct result. The theory of trials examines which procedures and rules of evidence, and the like, are best calculated to achieve this purpose consistent with the other ends of the law. Different arrangements for hearing cases may reasonably be expected in different circumstances to yield the right results, not always but at least most of the time.
    Thus, imperfect procedural justice incorporates the notion of an independent criterion for accuracy but adds the notion of "other ends of the law," e.g., considerations of cost that may be balanced against accuracy.
    The final notion is "pure procedural justice." Rawls writes:
      [P]ure procedural justice obtains when there is no independent criterion for the right result: instead there is a correct or fair procedure such that the outcome is likewise correct or fair, whatever it is, provided that the procedure has been properly followed. This situation is illustrated by gambling. If a number of persons engage in a series of fair bets, the distribution of cash after the last bet is fair, or at least not unfair, whatever this distribution is.
    Pure procedural justice rejects an underlying assumption of both perfect and imperfect procedural justice--the assumption that there is an independent criterion for what constitutes the correct outcome. There are not criteria for the correct outcome except for an ideal (or actual) set of procedures.
    Three Models of Procedural Justice: Accuracy, Balancing, and Participation Rawls's theory provides an abstract framework that can be used to categorize theories of procedural justice, but it doesn't tell us what the content of a theory of procedural justice might be. Three approaches have been characteristic of thinking about procedural justice--one emphasizes accuracy, the second cost, and the third participation. Each of these three approaches can be expressed as simply model of procedural justice:
      The Accuracy Model We can begin with the utopian hypothesis that the current doctrine is structured by an implicit conception of perfect procedural justice?the accuracy model?corresponding to the idea of perfect procedural justice. The core idea of this model is that the aim of procedure is a search for truth?e.g. conclusions of law that are correct and findings of fact that are true.
      But there are severe problems with the accuracy model. Given that civil procedure imposes real costs on litigants and society at large, it is difficult to argue that the smallest marginal gain in accuracy is worth the largest investment of resources. Justice has a price, and there is a point at which that price is not worth paying. Moreover, we have every reason to believe that accuracy is subject to the law of diminishing returns. If we were to make perfect accuracy our highest commitment, we would find that as we got closer and closer to our goal, the cost of reducing the marginal rate of error would become higher and higher. We will reach a point where society would be required to invest enormous resources for the most infinitesimal gain in accuracy.
      The Balancing Model The second model "the balancing model" corresponds to the idea of imperfect procedural justice. The consequentialist version of imperfect procedural justice finds substantial support in the decisions of the Supreme Court that interpret the Due Process Clauses of the United States Constitution. The most striking example is provided by the balancing test announced in Mathews v. Eldridge:
        [O]ur prior decisions indicate that identification of the specific dictates of due process generally requires consideration of three distinct factors: First, the private interest that will be affected by the official action; second, the risk of an erroneous deprivation of such interest through the procedures used, and the probable value, if any, of additional or substitute procedural safeguards; and finally, the Government's interest, including the function involved and the fiscal and administrative burdens that the additional or substitute procedural requirement would entail.
      Beginning with the emphasis on balancing in doctrine, we could construct a utilitarian conception of imperfect procedural justice. This effort is complicated, however, because there are many forms of utilitarianism; for our purposes, we might consider ideal rule utilitarianism, in which an act is right if and only if it is conformity with the system of rules, which if universally followed would produce the best consequences. Let us make a further simplifying assumption: that all of the relevant costs can be expressed as prices. The resultant approach will be roughly similar to some law and economics approaches.
      Consider for example, Richard Posner?s economic analysis of procedure. He writes, "The objective of a procedural system, viewed economically, is to minimize the sum of two costs. The first is "the cost of erroneous judicial decisions." The second type of cost is "the cost of operating the procedural system." Operating costs are borne by the public, in the form of subsidies to the judicial system and by the parties in the form of court fees, attorneys' fees, and litigation costs.
      The Participation Model The third model--the participation model?corresponds to the idea of pure procedural justice. The key notion is that it is it is participation in the process and not outcome that defines procedural justice. The second interpretation of the participation model connects the independent value of process with the dignity of those who are affected by legal proceedings. One way of articulating this central notion is that everyone is entitled to their day in court. This right to participation is justified by a background right of political morality, i.e. the right of persons (or citizens) to be treated with dignity and respect. A procedure which ensures parties an opportunity to participate in the process of making decisions that affect them might be counted as a just procedure for this reason, independently of the correctness of the outcome that results from the procedures.
      On influential version of the participation model has been developed by Jerry Mashaw. Mashaw states the intuitive idea as follows:
        At an intuitive level, a dignity approach is appealing. We all feel that process matters to us irrespective of result. This intuition may be a delusion. We may be so accustomed to rationalizing demands for improvement in our personal prospects, in the purportedly neutral terms of process fairness, that we can no longer distinguish between outcome-oriented motives and process-oriented arguments. * * * Yet there seems to be something to the intuition that process itself matters. We do distinguish between losing and being treated unfairly. And, however fuzzy our articulation of the process characteristics that yield a sense of unfairness, it is commonplace for us to describe process affronts as somehow related to disrespect for our individuality, to our not being taken seriously as persons.
      In recent years, the question whether participation has value that is independent of outcomes has been enormously controversial. The participation model reflects the view that participation matters for reasons other than cost and accuracy. Most advocates of the balancing model deny that participation has independent value--other than a subjective taste for participation which can be weighed in a cost-benefit analysis.
    Conclusion Of course, procedural justice is a very large topic, and we have only begun to scratch the surface. Law students encounter ideas about procedural justice in a variety of courses: Civil Procedure, Criminal Procedure, and Administrative Law are among the classes in which procedural justice may become an important focus of discussion. I hope this Lexicon post gives you a lively sense of the basic structure of legal thinking about procedural justice.
    Online Resource Bibliography
    • Robert Bone, Agreeing to Fair Process: The Problem with Contractarian Theories of Procedural Fairness, 83 B.U. L. REV. 485, 488-89 (2003).
    • Mathews v. Eldrige, 424 U.S. 319 (1976).
    • Jerry L. Mashaw, Due Process In The Administrative State (1985).
    • Richard Posner, Economic Analysis Of Law (1992).
    • John Rawls, A Theory Of Justice (1971)